BRITISH LIBRARY OF POLITICAL AND ECONOMIC SCIENCE LONDON SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS AND POLITICAL SCIENCE 10, PORTVGALSTREET, LONDON WC2A 2HD Tel. 01-405 7686 Fabian Tract 508 Freedom At Work: Towards The Refonn of Tory Employment Laws Chapter 1. Introduction I 2. Three Mistaken Approaches 8 3. The Case for Collective Freedom at Work 12 4. Collective Freedom at Work some examples 14 5. Freedom within Trade Unions 34 6. Freedom at Work and Community Interests 42 7. Summary and Conclusions 45 16/z.l ~.£ ' l NSS kO ~o'S'O M\2... Lord McCarthy is a Fellow of Nuffield College and University Lecturer in Industrial Relations at Oxford. He was Research Director of the Royal Commission on Trade Unions and Employers' Associations and served as an adviser to successive Labour Governments. He has been involved in industrial mediation and arbitration since 1968 and has chaired a great number of inquiries into industrial disputes. Since 1979 he has been Opposition front bench spokesman on Employment. This pamphlet like all publications of the Fabian Society represents not the collective view of the Society but only the views of the individual who prepared it. The responsibility of the Society is limited to approving the publications it issues as worthy for consideration within the labour movement. November 1985 ISBN 0 7163 0808 9 ISSN 0307 7523 Typeset by Character Typesetters (TU) 01-253 1766 Printed by Blackrose Press (TU) 01-2513043 Published by the Fabian Society, 11 Dartmouth Street, London SW1 H 9BN !.Introduction The Prime Minister is always telling the country that there is no alternative to her. Economic survival, she says, can only be based on her conviction that the activities of government must be further restricted. Industrial recovery, in her view, depends on allowing her Ministers to sell off even more of the public sector at knock down prices. Above all, there must be no halt to Thatcherite policies designed to remove all constraints on the operation of 'market forces'. Even within her own Cabinet this simple view of Britain's destiny has never gained unquestioned acceptance. Even within her own party there is a rising tide of objection to her combination of economic myopia and political inflexibility. In the country generally there are signs of a growing conviction that she has got it all wrong. Labour's alternative Labour has never accepted any of the fundamental assumptions ofThatcherism. In its most recent policy statement, A New Partnership: A New Britain , the Party has joined with the TUC to propose an alternative 'vision' based on public intervention, community responsibility and a more co-operative approach to Britain's long-standing and deep-seated problems. Labour argues that six years of Thatcher- ism have produced few lasting benefits. What has occurred is record unemployment, reductions in the size of our manufacturing base, neglect of the infrastructure and severe damage to the welfare state. At the same time Britain has become a much more divided and unequal society. To help reverse these developments Labour suggests a number of "priorities for action". These include a "programme for public investment and repair". This should make possible a revival of manufacture, improvements to the infrastructure, and allow for essential repairs to the worst hit parts of the welfare state. It will also provide up to a million new jobs. To help foster co-operation and support for such a programme Labour proposes an annual 'Economic Summit' to inaugurate "a new process of discussion and consultation with all sections of industry". On closer inspection the programme includes many novel features -some derived from lessons learned under previous Labour Governments, some extracted from the achievements of like- minded Governments in Scandinavia and Austria, some deduced from the evident failure of Thatcherite reliance on 'market forces'. But critics have rightly pointed out that there are important aspects of policy where the document provides little detailed guidance. Two answers can be made to criticisms of this kind. First, Mrs. Thatcher will probably hang on in Downing Street for another two years at least. There is surely ample time to amplify the more generalised and vague parts of the programme before an election manifesto is required. Second, much depends on what Mr. Kinnock finds when he gets to Downing Street. If, as is distinctly possible, there is a further decline in our relative competitiveness, or another burst of inflation , or the onset of another world recession , detailed plans will be in need of revision. Even major priorities may have to change. This pamphlet is written by one who supports the broad approach of A New Partnership: A New Britain and accepts the substance of both justifications for imprecision. It addresses itself to the limited but crucial question of what a future Labour Government should do about the present Government's industrial relations legislation ie the 1980 and 1982 Employment Acts and the 1984 Trade Union Act. But because workers are threatened with still more labour law, as the result of another Government Green Paper, it also refers to such matters as the Government's plans to cripple Wages Councils and their 1979 election pledge to curtail the right to strike' ih 'essential services'. It also says something about the best way to encourage a more productive and co-operative relationship between trade unions and a future Labour Government. There are at least four reasons. for undertaking such a task at the present time . The first is that on this subject the new policy document is vague to the point of being delphic. All it says is: "... the next Labour Government will repeal the present Government's divisive trade union legislation and replace it with positive legislation ". The electorate will want to know more than this and in the next twelve months attempts must be made to provide the outline of an answer. To this end several important motions were passed by the 1985 TUC. The most important committed the Congress, amongst other things: "To agree on a positive framework of law to extend collective bargaining and individual and collective rights at work". Another called for " A Bill of Rights for Working People" to include: ".. . statutory support for unions to achieve recognition and representation rights and to foster the development of trade unionism". No doubt as a result of these and other motions, the Employment Policy and Organisation Committee of the General Council will prepare a detailed and comprehensive report for consideration by next year's Congress. But once one starts to consider the issues and options involved in any detail they are found to be both complicated and controversial. It is therefore essential that those who wish to argue convincingly against what is still one of the more popular aspects of Thatcherite dogma should be both clear and united about what they want to put in its place. It is submitted that this can only be achieved after an open and frank debate which is not confined to the TUC. Second, the record of the past suggests that unless an incoming Government has thought through the legal consequences of what it wants to do in advance it will be no match for the judiciary. Trade union history is littere.::J with hastily concocted legal formulae which have failed to withstand the first assault of the courts. But until the Party itself decides what it wants the process of legal drafting cannot begin. Third , there is a distinct danger of starting off in the wrong direction-or at least not beginning in the best possible way. For this reason the following section begins by analysing three mistaken approaches, before advancing a case for the writer's preferred starting point. Finally, and most important of all, I believe that Labour has failed to stress sufficiently the close relationship which exists between what has been done in this field and so many other aspects of Tory policy. In many ways the Thatcherite 2 approach to trade union law and the rights of employees at the place of work epitomises so much that has been wrong over the last six years. To provide an acceptable alternative to the PM's mixture of prejudice and ignorance in this area of policy involves an assault on the very centre of her social and economic doctrine. Labour should welcome this challenge, but it is essential to take time, in advance, to get its side of the argument right. Partly for this reason most of the rest of this section is concerned with two essential preliminary points: first, a brief statement of the writer's own attitude towards trade unionism and the realities of the labour market; second a summary of the aims and intended effects of Tory legislation. The case for trade unionism The reader is entitled to know something of the author's assumptions and prejudices in a didactic work of this sort. In any case, an alternative legal framework to that provided by the Tories must be rooted in a quite different view of the value and achievements of trade unionism in contemporary Britain. My approach is that of a life-long member of the Labour Party who is also a trade unionist. But it is also that of an academic who has spent most of the last twenty-five years trying to study management and trade unions in as objective a way as possible. In addition I am aware that my reactions to problems of industrial conflict have also been significantly influenced by involvement as a mediator and arbitrator of industrial disputes-which are often partly caused by the mistakes and omissions of government. This varied experience has resulted in both convictions and doubts which can be briefly summarised. First, I remain convinced that great value is to be attached to the maintenance and development of a free trade union movement able to respond to the wishes and demands of its members. I do not believe that the average worker can hope to bargain with an employer on anything like equal terms without the benefit of combination. It seems to me that the employment relationship remains essentially one of dependence, where the interests of the parties to the employment contract are not identical though they are not inevitably opposed in all respects. Genuine and deeply felt grievances are bound to arise between workers and those who manage or employ them. Collective bargaining remains the best means I know of channelling and structuring worker demands so that they can be considered and resolved without frequent and damaging resort to industrial action. In view of their essential role in the process of collective bargaining, union leaders have been rightly termed the " managers of discontent" by the American sociologist C. Wright Mills. Second, more positive arguments for free trade unionism can be deployed. It is only through their membership of unions that workers can hope to participate effectively in management decisions and give concrete expression to the age-old aspirations of industrial democracy. Through the right kind of procedures for consultation and negotiation they can contribute greatly to the quality of management decisions, and come to appreciate their necessary involvement in the aims and achievements of the enterprise that employs them. Thus I believe that trade unions can contribute to maintaining and improving industrial and organisational efficiency, but only if their essential role as the representatives of their members is fully understood and appreciated by management. Finally , and with increasing emphasis and urgency today, my conviction is that the legal status of trade unionism has become linked to the preservation of political democracy. Unless a Govern 3 ment accepts that workers must be free to combine, and occasionally use the strength that comes from combination, the basis of political pluralism is undermined. As Colin Crouch has rightly argued, taken to its extremes the doctrine he terms neo-laisser fa ire, which lies behind so much of Government policy, is essentially authoritarian and centrist. As he puts it: " It assumes a strong, if democratically elected, central Government, powerful enough ro resisr secrionalist pressurefor more jobs or higher levels of publicexpenditure".' In this sense it aims to place such decisions "beyond the reach of democratic politics", so that they can be regulated by the so-called 'invisible hand' of the market. I also agree with Crouch when he says that the supporters of the doctrine of neo-laisser faire must, in the end, be willing to use the " most coercive and least democratically responsible organs of the state" -ie the police and the armed forces -to undermine the power of organised labour. For what they are determined to prevent at all costs is: "derailed government interference wirh the rights ofproperty owners, and ifthe cosr of doing this is considerable inrerference with other kinds of liberry, rh en so be ir". Of course many people believe that academics are better off without convictions of the kind I have summarised above. They are thought to interfere with objectivity and result in the suppression of evidence. I have never accepted this view. If it were to be admitted there would be few readable books to give students. The founding fathers of ocial science-from Plato to Keynes -would all need to be removed from the reading li st. In any case the existence of convictions and beliefs does not prevent the presence of doubt, or destroy the capacity for critical appraisal. Because one favours the existence of trade unionism one does not need to deny that like other well estab lished and long-standing British institu tions they can be bureaucratic, illiberal, incompetent and myopic; just like Parlia ment , the armed services, the Treasury, the Bank of England, British business and the Hebdomadal Council of Oxford Uni versity. It is certainly not necessary to pretend that the results of collective bargaining are universally beneficial , or that they have never contributed to the problem of cost induced inflation. It can be admitted that if Britain had a Government which took effective action to expand the economy and create additional jobs, it is possible that, before long, the rate of increase in pay settlements would rise. This could help to produce a situation in which rising prices affected Britain's ability to compete in world markets. It would make it more difficult for any Government to sustain 'high-growth', 'high employment' policies. One can also grant that the primary aim of all industrial action by trade unions is to put pressure on recalcitrant employers, even if the result is inconvenience to the public. It merely does not follow from all this that an attempt should be made to legislate trade unions out of existence, rather than enlist their aid in dealing with common problems. It certainly cannot be demonstrated that if their influence could be destroyed in this way significant and immediate benefits would follow. For example, I know of no convincing empirical study which supports the view that trade union wage bargaining has been responsible for most of the major defects and weaknesses of the British economy- many of which developed at a time when union power was far weaker than at any period since the end of the war. I can cite a great deal of evidence to suggest that defective marketing, poor design, inadequate financial institutions and an absence of the right kind of government 4 assistance have been of far greater importance.' I also believe that the record suggests that trade unions -and trade union leaders-can co-operate effectively in the achievement of worthwhile government objectives if they are actually listened to and taken into account. The problem has been that in the past even Labour Governments have become hard of hearing in the end. Dogma and prejudice Unfortunately, since 1979, we have had Ministers who do not even pretend to listen -except to those who reflect and pander to their prejudices. Moreover, even in the groves of academe, Jet alone the media, it has proved increasingly difficult to discuss the complex of social, economic and institutional variables which actually govern the labour market and circumscribe the behaviour and influence of trade unions in the real world. The public debate has been captured and dominated by the more dogmatic and unreasoning supporters of Thatcherite doctrine. Curiously enough, specialists in my subject have not known how to deal with this invasion of their territory-except to complain that it is all very complicated and hand round a book list. But the new entrants to the debate have shown no sign of wanting to read our books. They have remained unreservedly committed to a view of the relationship between wages, employment and union power to which no decent labour market text book would give any credence. Their position is, of course, most simply stated in what are now the astonishingly influential writings of the Prime Minister's favourite guru -Professor F.A. van Hayek. He has long argued that it is only trade union constraint on wages, as a result of the process of collective bargain ing, which prevents the cost of labour from falling to a point where more or less full employment will again be possible in Britain. He has also pioneered the view that union power, in some sense which he has never defined, belongs to national trade union leaders, and is rooted in their ability to exploit legal 'immunities' which have existed with some interruptions and modifications ever since 1906.' Moreover, since 1979 disciples of Professor van Hayek have developed his ideas to a point where they have become a fashionable and precise orthodoxy. Thus his most quoted disciple, Professor Patrick Minford, has actually sought to calculate how far Britain's economic decline into mass unemployment can be blamed on trade unions. His verdict is that since the proportion of workers in unions rose by 13 per cent from 1963 to 1979, this must be the main reason why 'total real wages' rose by the same amount and led to an 8.5 per cent reduction in output and the destruction of a million jobs since 1963.' (How it has come about since 1979 union density has been falling while unemployment has risen by more than two and a half million has not been explained.) Yet because the Prime Minister and leading members of her Government have come to believe assertions of this kind, the contribution which trade unionism can make to the defence of worker interests and the management of the economy has been ignored or derided by Government spokesmen. At the same time Britain has had a succession of Jaws which have severely restricted the legal right to combine. It is my conviction that the Conservative Party first embarked on its 'step by step' attack on trade union rights because it was thought to be electorally popular- and in the aftermath of the 1979 'Winter of Discontent' this was undoubtedly the case. But I am equally persuaded that the Prime Minister and her closest colleagues have continued to travel this route because of their growing addiction to van 5 Hayek 'free market' principles in general. With the collapse of 'Friedmanite' policies for controlling the economy by manipulating the mysterious and slippery M3, there must have seemed to be, in Mrs. Thatcher's favourite phrase, "no real alternative". Thus in their attempts to assist the fumbled gropings of the 'hidden hand ', Government has been led to abandon its responsibilities for managing the economy and protecting the public over an ever wider field. Controls on capital and foreign exchange have been abandoned. Hire purchase rates and bank lending have been 'set free'. Regulations governing air services and the licensing of lorries and long distance coaches have been relaxed. Planning requirements have been eased, or abolished. Free-ports and enterprise zones have been set up as tax havens. Development taxes, stamp duties and investment surcharges have all been repealed. All, or part, of half a dozen national assets have been sold off to speculators at rock bottom prices-eight more are to be privatised before the next election. 'Contracting out' has been forced on the NHS and local authorities- even where they could show that the result was higher costs and lower services. Given such a climate of ideological dogma, there was no hope of a let up in the stream of anti-union legislation designed to 'improve the working of the labour market'. Nevertheless, it is important to note just how far the Government has already travelled. The details of what has been done, and the consequences for working people, are elaborated in subsequent sections. However, it is necessary to begin with a brief summary of what was intended and achieved. seriously narrowed the ambit of lawful strike action -most effectively by providing a much more limited definition of what is to count as a trade dispute. Second, they have added very significantly to the financial cost of straying beyond those narrow limits -above all by removing the immunity for actions in tort within the context of a trade dispute. The result is that it is now much more likely that employers, or injured third parties, will take unions and their members to court- especially since it now seems that interim injunctions imposing restraints backed by quasi-criminal penalties are readily available from the courts. Third, the new labour laws have fastened on trade unicns a whole series of legal tests and standards more stringent than those which exist in any other democratic country. In my opinion no organisation dependent on voluntary help could hope to comply with all of these regulations -for example, the totally impractical requirements of the 1984 Act for an up-to-date and accurate central register of union members. The effect could well be that over the next few years a rash of contested elections and union decisions will be challenged in the courts, many of which will undoubtedly be sponsored by disaffected and hostile right-wing groups. Fourth, the Government has removed most of the props and aids to union organisation which have been traditionally designed to help workers organise in areas where the employer is unusually powerful -most recently through the abolition of the 'Fair Wages' resolution and the forthcoming attack on Wages Councils. Scope and limitations The legal assauH on trade unionism It should be clear by now that this pamphlet is addressed to those who have First, the Acts of 1980, 1982 and 1984 have remained unimpressed by Thatcherite 6 attempts to raise their naive version of neo-classical economic dogma to the status of a religious principle. It is intended for those who still feel that in the labour market, as elsewhere, one must try to formulate policy on the reasonable assumption that the advantages of price competition, or the abandonment of all forms of collective regulation, should be matters for empirical inquiry, rather than blind faith. From this point on these assumptions are more or less taken for granted. What the pamphlet seeks to provide, in some detail in some cases, are the main factors to be taken into account if the present labour laws are to be refashioned on the basis ofsuch assumptions. This means that I must usually begin with a briefaccount of what the present Government has done in a particular field and its likely consequences. It should also be stressed that what is advanced is in no way comprehensive. Very little is said about the working of Industrial Tribunals since 1971 although there is a considerable body of evidence to suggest that they are in need of modification. The way in which protection against unfair dismissal , or discrimination , needs to be improved, is not discussed in any detail. Several large questions, such as the case for a more extended use ofTripartite Courts, are not touched on at all. Others, such as the future boundaries of lawful secondary action, are not considered in specific terms. The very important issue of the role of the police in industrial disputes and demonstrations is only dealt with tangentially via a review of picketing law. The excuse is partly length, but also the fact that one naturally tends to focus on areas where one thinks one has some idea of what should be done. It should also be appreciated that what follows is very much a personal view, which must not be taken commit anybody but its author. I doubt if every proposal would find favour with all active trade unionists, or their leaders. On the other hand , I have reason to believe that much of what I suggest would not be challenged by quite a number of employers especially those with some day to day experience of industrial relations. It should also be all too evident that this pamphlet was not written by a lawyer. Fortunately it has been read by one, but he is in no way responsible for any errors, infelicities or mistakes that remain.' I also hope that it wi ll be appreciated that the proposals below are not advanced in any dogmatic spirit. They are there to assist debate, in the hope that they will stimulate thought. The rest of the pamphlet is divided into seven chapters. In chapter two, I consider three frequently canvassed ways of replacing the present legislation. I regard each of these as a non-starter, but it is important to say why. In chapter three I advance my own approach. This focusses on the case for effective freedom at work. It suggests that Labour should concentrate on creating worker rights, rather than the return of trade union 'immunities'. Chapter four contains four illustrations of how to apply the preferred approach to important areas of the law-ie the use of industrial action, the closed shop, the right to picket and union recognition. Each of these involve the establishment of rights which are mainly exercised against the employer. In chapter five the pamphlet considers that area of the law which estalishes rights for union members vis a vis their union. In chapter six, a number of wider questions are considered briefly-notably how best to ensure that the restoration of effective freedom at work by a Labour Government remains compatible with the interests of the community as a whole. Chapter seven contains a summary of the argument and lists my positive proposals for a new legal framework. 7 2. Three Mistaken Approaches The first approach which I regard as a non-starter maintains that all Labour needs to do is to repeal everything the Tories have done since 1979 and restore the position as it was when Labour left office. There are at least two things wrong with this proposal. First, and with the undoubted benefit of hindsight, it is clear that the Acts of 1974-1978 were le s than perfect. One area where this was undoubtedly so concerns the ease with which judges have continued to grant injunctions against trade unions. Another relates to the whole question of trade union recognition, where employers like Grunwick were able to ignore the intended effects of the legislation. Then there were a number of complicated legal issues that were never solved by the Labour Government -such as the lack of an acceptable definition for 'peaceful picketing' or the proper role of the police in industrial disputes. Another problem related to the enforcement of union membership agreements (UMAs) -especially after the three railwaymen, who were dismissed on grounds of non- unionism, won their case before the European Court of Human Rights. In other words, as we shall see when we come to consider what needs to be done in all these areas, it will not be enough merely to restore the provisions of the 1974, 1975 and 1976 legislation. They need to be improved upon in the light of experience. Recent developments But it is not only that Labour could not hope to get everything right last time. Times and attitude have changed . T here have been a number of important developments, both in the law and in industrial relations. Some of these have concerned a number of well-publicised disputes and the way they have been reported in the media. Others have arisen from inter-union relations and the processes of union government. Much of the Tory legislation-notably Parts 1 and 2 of the Act of 1984 -were presented to the public as an attempt to deal with such developments, albeit in a partisan way. Without suggesting that they were either justified or practical, it seems clear to me that the electorate will expect more from Labour than a simple pledge to repeal them. Indeed, I doubt if this will be a practical option by the time of the next election-if only because some have already begun to make an impact on union behaviour and government. One area where this is undoubtedly the case concerns the election of union executives. Another is the procedures used to authorise industrial action. In any case the common law has long exercised a significant jurisdiction over many aspects of internal union affiar -although it intervention has not always been constructive or helpful. Labour will certainly need to advance its own proposals in areas of this kind, and these will need to be capable of gaining general support. Finally, in recent years, British membership of the EEC has meant that a number of directives and draft directives have been di cussed within the Commun 8 ity which have a direct bearing on employee rights at work. The present Government has tended to oppose , and even veto proposals of this kind, whenever it could be argued that they interfered with the operation of a 'free market'. Labour will hardly wish to echo this approach and therefore it needs to make up its own mind about such initiative Priorities The second mistaken approach is to assume that if simple repeal and replacement is not the answer, then we must grind slowly through all sections of Tory legislation in an effort to produce an all- embracing draft bill in time for the next election. This would take far too long; the electorate wants to know. at least in broad terms, what Labour will do in the near future. A more complex objection is that Labour needs to decide its priorities. In effect we require our own 'step by step· approach. To take two examples. It is essential that on entry into office we should know exactly what we want to do about labour injunctions eg applications to a court for orders to 'restrain' unions who are contemplating or involved in industrial action of some kind. In 1974 Labour provided that the courts should not grant such injunctions where unions, or their members, were "likely" to be able to sustain a "trade dispute defence". Given the incursions which the Tories have made into the scope of the trade dispute defence -eg where disputes involve off-site pickets or sympathetic action-this provides very limited protection today. But there is a further problem. Experience suggests that even if the 1974-6 definition of a trade dispute were restored, or even extended, it might not prevent judges from granting injunctions against unions where the plaintiff could show that there was 'a serious issue to be tried' and that the balance of convenience favoured the preservation of the status quo. On this basis employers and third parties have recently obtained injunctions to protect them from the threat of any trading loss once a dispute begins. The effect on union solidarity and morale of imposing what becomes an indefinite ban on all forms of collective action, backed by the ultimate threat of quasi-criminal sanctions in the form of an action for contempt, has not really been considered by the judges. Many ways out of the problem have been proposed. First, it could be made . more difficult for employers and others to obtain ex parte injunctions ie those granted in the absence of union representatives on grounds of urgency. Second, a statute could specify that all evidence submitted by the plaintiff should be subject to cross examination. More significantly, perhaps, the plaintiff might be required to provide stronger evidence that the trade dispute defence was likely to fail if the case went to trial. Most important of all, in my opinion, action could be taken to alter the 'balance of convenience' test, so that judges were less likely to assume that an indefinite postponement of all forms of industrial action was invariably in the interests of both sides. This is a tricky but technical problem, which i not inherently controversial so far as the labour movement is concerned. The crucial need is to have a number of complementary proposals ready for immediate enactment; a paragraph or so which friendly experts feel should do the job. Ifthey should turn out to be less than watertight then Labour must be ready with further amendments. The position is much more complex and debatable in the area of trade union recognition. This issue poses much more than technical problems. Here, in 1975, Labour followed the proposals of the 1968 Royal Commission on Trade Unions and Employers' Associations. As has been noted they had little effect and ACAS 9 calculated that in four years a mere 15,000 trade unionists obtained recognition as a result. Yet there were many disputes within the trade union movement over who had the right to demand recognition under the new legislation. By the time the legislation was repealed most unions took the view that it was little or no use to them. Since then many union officials have come to believe that the law cannot provide effective help against anti-trade union employers while its very existence may discourage employers in general from coming to terms with trade unions in their firms. I think this judgement is both premature and potentially disastrous. On the other hand, I readily accept that if there is to be legislation to encourage representation and recognition it wi ll need to be thought out with much more care than last time. In chapter four I advance my own ideas on the subject, but I would not expect everything I suggest to be embodied as it stands in instant legislation. Some of my proposals would take time to put into effect, others might need to be modified in the light of experience. Meanwhile Labour should think about the options available and their likely consequences. Until then it does not need to say much more than that it is determined to try to improve on its previous record. Rights and immunities So I come to the third and fina l nonstarter. It is the assertion that all we need to do is recast our traditional system of 'negative immunities' into what is referred to as 'the language of positive rights'. This is really no more than the wrong way to begin or rather the wrong approach to regard as the key to all problems. Of course there is something in this approach. The Government continues to make play of the fact that for largely historical reasons the position of British unions in law, and the right of their members to engage in industrial action , has been defined in negative terms ie as a series of 'immunities' from common law liability, such as inducing a breach of contract, or combining 'in restraint of trade'. The fact that these freedoms have been defined as 'immunities' has enabled those who have known better, plus those who have merely been ignorant, to suggest that trade unions in Britain have been placed 'above and beyond the law'. It has been asserted that for most of the period since the passage of the Trades Disputes Act in 1906, unions and their members have enjoyed 'unique' privileges and a degree of 'protection' denied to ordinary citizens. Consequently it has been plausible to present the legislation of the 1980s as nothing more sinister than a partial redressing of the balance -a modest and over-due attempt to bring trade union barons and their acolytes within the 'rule of law'. T he fact that the result has been the most restrictive labour code in Western Europe, which in certain respects involves an invasion of union autonomy without precedent in western democracies, has been largely ignored. A way must be found to break through this systematic misrepresentation. After all, those of us who have tried to combat the misrepresentation so far have gone out of our way to emphasise that what Britain terms a common law immunity is usually a positive statutory right in other countries -often embodied in a written constitution which it is difficult to reduce or withdraw. Thus other EEC countries have a 'right to strike' and a 'right to representation' -often in a more extended form than that which now exists in Thatcherite Britain. And of course the existence of rights of this kind involves a circumscription of the legal claims of other groups -such as employers and injured third parties. They are not able to sue unions, or their officials, on the mere grounds that their 'interests' have been 10 damaged by the exercise of such rights. Otherwise action by the unions and members could not be said to be legal in the first place. Once this point is taken it becomes possible to compare the rights accorded to unions and their members in different countries-although this is still far from an easy task. It becomes reasonable to suggest that even before 1979 the comparative position in Britain was not universally favourable to workers or their organisations eg in respect of the right to withdraw labour without risk of breach of contract. It seems reasonable to go on and argue that next time Labour should present its proposed alternative framework in similarly positive terms , avoiding the negative language of immunities and stressing the parallels with what exists elsewhere. There is clearly something to be said for this view, so long as it realised what is being suggested is largely presentational, advocated in the hope that it will avoid or counter a form of criticism that is unfair and calculated to mislead . But it is essential to hang on to the point that by speaking the language of rights we do not actually solve any of the major problems. On the contrary, as Lord Wedderburn has rightly argued in his contribution to the debate , whatever language one uses , the propositions that result still require definition. Moreover, as he says, "such definition of basic concepts of labour law constitute 'limiting factors' determining the scope of rights available to employers, workers and trade unions".' In other words, changing the form of the words used does not , in itself, force judges to be more judicious and balanced in their consideration of worker interests when asked to grant injunctions. It will not necessarily prevent management from sacking shop stewards. It is unlikely to make a significant contribution to the complex problem of safeguarding both public order and the right peacefully to persuade on a picket line. Above all , it will not tell us where we should draw the line between the conflicting claims and interests of workers , employers and injured third parties. It will not help us to decide what Labour should do about such topics as the closed shop, union elections or strike ballots. It has even been suggested , by some labour lawyers, that it may make these problems more difficult to solve. For if we rewrite the whole of British labour law using the language of rights, rather than immunities, it could be less easy to prescribe with the required degree of exactness what is intended by Parliament. It might be more difficult to anticipate , in advance, how judges will react to laws couched in what they will regard as 'novel' ie. 'unusual' forms. (Indeed some say they are likely to interpret them even more restrictively, whenever they see the chance.) Certainly, as Wedderburn also points out, those bits of past labour law which have been defined in terms of 'rights' rather than 'immunities', have not remained immune from the process of judical review. (For example, the 'positive right' to picket as embodied in the 1906 and 1974 legislation.) All this is not to say that Labour should avoid referring to its proposals in terms of rights; as I have said, in presentational terms there are good reasons for doing so. All I am claiming at the moment is that this should not be taken to the point where it prejudges and predetermines the ultimate language to be used in a future statute. It also must be fully realised that very little is solved by substituting one language for another. Meanwhile I still have to advance my own preferred approach to these problems. 11 3. The Case for Collective Freedom at Work I would like to see Labour focus on the case for establishing effective freedom at work, stressing the extent to which this is dependent upon a legal framework of individual rights which make collective action possible. Of course freedom is a word which is almost never off the lips of Tory politicians nowadays. The Prime Minister cannot get through a single Parliamentary Question Time without posing as a freedom fighter at least twice. But when she uses the term it has nothing whatever to do with the freedom of workers to act in concert. It is usually part of a case for more privatisation, or reductions in the scope and cost of the social services. Insofar as an extension of liberty is involved what is said to be needed is a reduction in the 'burdens' of businessmen-especially those of less than average size. (A fondness for diminutive businessmen has become an essential element in Thatcherite ideology.) Thatcherite freedom No concern is shown for the day to day problems of the average employee except when it is alleged that the employment protection laws, which the Government inherited , are threatening jobs by limiting the 'freedom' of businessmen to respond to 'market forces'. Of course with this objective in mind, freedom has been invoked to narrow the definition of what is to count as an unfair dismissal. The period over which employers are free to dismiss unfairly has also been extended. All forms of employment protection have been removed from those unfortunate enough to work for sufficiently small businessmen. At the same time the Government has refused to support action within the EEC to provide a right to parental leave, or protection for part-time workers. Meanwhile EEC directives on equal pay for work of equal value have been emasGulated . As is well known all the evidence we have -for the most part derived from surveys sponsored by the Government itself -does not support the view that employment protection legislation in Britain has affected the ability of employers of all sizes to compete-either at home or abroad. It suggests, on the contrary, that businessmen have been much more concerned about repeated changes in Government taxation policy, or high interest rates, or the reluctance of British banks to provide long term risk capital. Since the Government came to office these have been the real restrictions on output and employment growth. As a result it should be easy for a Labour Government to pledge action designed to restore and extend individual employment protection law, so far as it 12 affects areas such as unfair dismissal and race and sex discrimination. There seems to be no good reason why British standards in so many respects should lag behind those that have existed in most European countries or, in the case of sex and race discrimination , the USA and Canada. Collective bargaining What is not so widely understood, even on the left , is the connection between individual employment rights and collective trade union immunities. Yet trade unions were founded and developed because workers wished to exercise some rights at work collectively. Most importantly, they wished to be free to act in concert to attempt to influence their pay and conditions; to substitute collective bargaining for individual bargaining. It is worth exploring briefly why this should be so. The individual worker who lacks the right to combine must either accept the terms dictated by the employer or leave the job -in effect he withdraws his labour, but does so as an individual. Since there are many more employees, and would-be employees, than there are employers, and since the employer has more resources at his disposal , the strongest party in any bargain to be struck on these terms is bound to be the employer. This fact is sometimes referred to as the 'natural' power of the employer in an unorganised labour market. It is the reason why employment is termed a 'dependent' or 'subordinate' relationship. The subordinate nature of the employment relationship justifies the existence of individual employment rights against the employer -eg the right to complain of unfair dismissal. But it also lies behind the granting of a legal right to combine. Suppose the individual worker has a legal right to combine. He or she joins a trade union and seeks to negotiate on a collective basis with the employer. Any disagreement over terms and conditions can now be expressed collectively, so long as a group of employees, or would-be employees, can agree on their common demands. There are still more employers than employees, and the natural power of the employer in the labour market is therefore not destroyed. But there is a significant difference. By acting in concert, and selecting a representative to put their point of view, employees have some chance of 'matching' the natural power of the employer. If they still cannot reach agreement they may also decide to withdraw their labour-but this time they do so collectively. Faced with a collective refusal to work the employer is more likely to modify his demands and the workers concerned have more chance of obtaining a settlement that is in their interests as well as those of their employer. But once demands for the right to bargain collectively emerge, society must decide how far workers should be encouraged or permitted to act in this way . For example, should they be allowed to form permanent organisations with funds and leaders who are responsible to . them? Should they be free to decide the terms on which they will agree to withdraw labour collectively-even if employers and third parties complain that the results damage their interests or inconvenience the public? Or should the state seek to prescribe the way in which unions are organised and make use of the right to withdraw labour collectively? Should there be a series of legal penalties and liabilities that circumscribe and limit collective freedom at work? There are other issues to be resolved as well. Suppose employers refuse to meet union leaders and bargain with them collectively? Suppose they combine to undermine and resist the right to collective bargaining? Should the law intervene to limit their freedom to act against unions and their members: thus extending the 13 individual's right to collective freedom in a much more positive way? The link between the individual's rights at work and the legal position of trade unions should now be clear enough. It is not possible to provide collective rights for individuals without legalising trade unions and affording them some degree of protection and immunity. Trade union rights are needed to make collective rights effective for individuals. They are not 'privileges' extracted from a reluctant or acquiescent state; they flow from society's prior decision to grant the right to combine to employees. If they did not exist it would either be necessary to legislate on a wide front to protect employees from the consequences of an abuse of employer power -or the labour market would remain in its 'natural' state with the balance of power slanted towards employers as a whole. Given the Thatcher Government's obsessional need to remove all restrictions on the operation of a 'free market', they can no longer be relied upon to accept the validity of arguments of this kind. Without openly denying the need for combination in any form , the hard liners in the Government are more and more inclined to blame the mere existence oftrade union combination and the process of collective bargaining for a whole series of longstanding defects in the British economy and British public life. Certainly, members of the Cabinet, most notably the Prime Minister and her Chancellor of the Exchequer, assert almost daily that a further reduction in union influence is essential if their plans for a market based recovery are to have any chance of success. What Labour needs to emphasise is that in the name of this mythology laws intended to increase union liability have already been taken to the point where the individual's freedom to combine has been significantly affected. The need to reestablish collective freedom at work, in the name of the workers themselves, should form the cornerstone of Labour's approach to the reform of the present labour laws. 4. Collective Freedom at Work- some examples A. Freedom to withdraw labour The most obvious area where recent changes in the law have had an impact on collective freedom at work concerns the so called 'right to strike'. This is a complex subject and to explain what has happened one 14 must begin with the consequences of the notorious Taff Vale judgement of 1901. In that case the House of Lords ruled that unions were liable for damages caused by their agents who were found to have organised or 'induced' a breach of employment contracts. Since breach of contract is actionable by the party to the contract who suffers the breach, the unions concerned were said to have brought about an unlawful act ie a civil wrong or 'tort'. They were also made subject to interlocutory or interim injunctions intended to restrain them from committing such torts. Refusal to obey could lead to an action for quasi-criminal contempt. Legal background Following Taff Yale many unions faced actions for damages. It proved extremely difficult to organise or sanction industrial action without incurring some form of contractual liability. The Act of 1906 sought to deal with this problem by protecting inducement within the context of a 'trade dispute'. In effect it granted tortious immunity to the agents of workers and employers engaged in a dispute over terms and conditions of work. From the viewpoint of unions and their officials this meant that they were no longer liable, even where their members withdrew their labour collectively in ways that involved a breach of employment contracts. At this time this appeared to be all that was required to re-establish the right to strike. What was left unsettled, amongst other things, was the circumstances in which the original breach arose. What the Act failed to specify was how the individual worker, who wished to withdraw his labour in concert with others, went about avoiding damage to his own contract. This was left to the decisions of the judges. Fortunately, or unfortunately, there turned out to be almost no case for the judges to decide for some time after 1906. Since unions and their officials were thought to be immune from all forms of contract liability, few employers considered it worth establishing whether or not their own workers had struck in breach of contract. In this vacuum there grew up a doctrine most clearly expressed by Professor Otto Kahn-Freund in his seminal account of British labour law, as it was understood at the time, published in 1954. Kahn-Freund's view was that the issue of legality, from the viewpoint of the individual worker, turned on the adequacy or otherwise of the period of notice given by the worker to the employer. As he put it: "... If, in a particular trade, there is a custom to the effect that employers and workers can terminate their contracts without notice, a lock-out or strike cannot be illegal by reason of it being a breach of contract. But if there is usually a term of notice of, say, a fortnight, the workers are liable to damages if they quit without giving this notice". ' Whether notice could be given on the workers' behalf, say by their union officials at national level, Kahn-Freund did not consider. Insofar as trade union officials thought about the problem, they tended to assume that this was the case. Unfortunately, as Wedderburn argued in The Worker and the Law in 1965, it now appears that Kahn-Freund was wrong• Successive cases have established that even if notice equal to the period specified in the contract is given personally, by each individual striker, most forms of industrial action inevitably involve the workers concerned in a breach of contract. It is difficult to underestimate the significance of this development, from the viewpoint IS of both workers and trade unions. But it is essential to understand what has happened if Labour is to provide a more equitable and balanced legal framework which restores the right to strike. First, it means that there is no freedom to withdraw labour in Britain, in the sense that in most cases the workers involved have laid themselves open to an action for breach of contract. They. have also committed an unlawful act, and if the result produces damage to the employer, they may be liable to a civil action claiming compensation. More importantly, perhaps, the very act of striking almost certainly absolves the employer from any obligations he may have under the worker's existing contract of employment. In effect the worker can be dismissed , instantly, without compensation or money in lieu of notice. Moreover, what the employer has done is in no sense 'unfair' in law -it does not give rise to compensation of grounds of unfair dismissal. But the circumscription of collective freedom at work has not stopped at this point. Obviously since virtually all strikes are now known to give rise to illegality, it becomes more important than ever that the protections first established in 1906, as subsequently qualified and clarified in 1974-6, should continue to operate. In fact , the reverse has been the case especially since 1980. Liabilities To begin with the courts have developed an additional liability where strike action may be said to involve breach of 'commercial contracts' -a possibility not considered in 1906. Second, under the provisions of the 1980 Employment Act it has become actionable for workers or trade union officials to be present or involved in 'off- site' picketing, or to participate in or organise a wide range of 'secondary action'. Attempts to enforce union membership agreements have also been made actionable in a variety of ways. Third, as a result of the 1982 Act the definition of what is to count as a trade dispute has been significantly narrowed- so that it does not cover anything other than a dispute over the worker's own terms and conditions limited to his own place of work. Most important of all, section 15 of the 1982 Act specifically removes the protections of the 1906 Act, where any form of liability arises out of the actions of union members and/or their officials, if the act complained of can be shown to have been "endorsed" or "authorised" by the union or one of its agents. Given all these developments it is obvious enough what needs to be done. For the first time in British history a right to withdraw labour collectively must be clearly established. The basic requirement is that in deciding to act in concert, for the purpose of improving or defending terms and conditions of employment, the individual worker must be able to avoid liability for breach of the employment contract. Whatever the legal formula adopted to secure this objective it should be recognised as the fundamental aim of Labour's new legal framework. The simplest way to proceed would be to provide that in future liability for contract breach would be limited to situations outside the context of a trade dispute. Given that workers are taking action in contemplation or furtherance of trade dispute, then no court should entertain an action against them for breach of contract. Of course a statement of this kind need not prejudge certain other related issues -notably the question of whether or not, and in what circumstances, employers should retain an ultimate right to dismiss workers who go on strike eg after due notice, or on certain conditions. My own view on this question is that in broad terms the position in the 1978 Act of the last 16 Labour Government represents the basis of a satisfactory compromise. Section 62 of the Act allowed for dismissal provided that none of the workers involved were afterwards offered selective reemployment. This was termed the 'picking and choosing rule', since it was intended to prevent the selective victimisation of shop stewards and other so called 'militants'. Unfortunately, under section 9 of the 1982 Act, the scope of the picking and choosing rule was narrowed , so that it now only prevents victimisation within a given establishment at the date of the dismissal of the complainant. Thus, the employer who sees any erosion of strike action is free to 'pick off' the workers taking part, by dismissal plant by plant. This has been rightly termed "a blot on the law of unfair dismissal" which Labour must erase.• What would also be essential is a proper definition of what is to count as a trade dispute. Clearly the present restricted definition set out in section 18 of the 1982 Act is in need of widening. It ought not to rule out all forms of secondary action. It should not prevent the enforcement of all forms of union membership agreement. Once again , in broad terms there needs to be a return to something like the scope of the definition before Conservative amendment -but many of the issues involved are considered in more detail below. The point to be made at the moment is more narrow but more fundamental. The aim must be fully to legalise what workers do themselves ie to obtain for them a right to take collective action in concert with other workers. Once this is done the legal position of their unions is transformed. 'ihey are assisting in a lawful act. They can no longer be presented as the fomenters and encouragers of illegality who need to be protected from the 'normal' consequences of such action by a series of ever more complex immunities. On the contrary, they can resume their proper role as the agents of their members , enjoying rights which are no longer singular or unique to those enjoyed by unions in other countries. B. Freedom to work with union members only A second area where changes in the legal framework have affected the right to combine concerns the controversial subject of the closed shop ie situations where employment is made conditional on membership of one of a specified number of trade unions. Once again what needs to be done cannot be explained without a somewhat extended account of how the present position has emerged, notably the way in which successive Governments have sought to deal with the question of whether or not dismissal on grounds of non-unionism should be regarded as 'unfair'. Before the establishment of a right to compensation in cases of unfair dismissal , the legal position of the closed shop was fairly straightforward. It had been established that workers had the right to refuse to work with non-unionists so long as their reasons for acting in this way was a desire to defend or advance their trading interests. In this way the legal position was said to be the same as that which applied to commercial monopolies or cartels who had long been allowed to refuse to deal with non-members, and even refuse them membership, without threat of legal penalty. So long as the motive of the combination was not 'malice' or 'spite' against an individual , no question of damages could arise. This situation was inevitably complicated by the creation of the concept of unfair dismissal in 1971. The question then arose: was it to be regarded as 'fair' to dismiss a worker on grounds of non- unionism? And if it was unfair, who was liable for the compensation? Under the 1971 Industrial Relations Act the Heath Government made the closed shop unlaw 17 ful in all its forms. But a number of alternative ways of maintaining "union security" were provided for "registered unions". The most important of these was the right to what was termed an "agency shop"-a form of modified closed shop well known in the United States. In any agency shop a worker who refused to join a union, or resigned his or her membership, was offered two alternatives to dismissal: (i) The chance to make a "service payment" to the union with an agency shop agreement which was equal to the sum required to become and remain a member. (ii) The chance to make an equivalent payment to a charity of their choice, which need not be connected to the trade union movement in any way. It was only where workers refused to adopt either of these options that dismissal on grounds of non-unionism was to be regarded as fair. Unfortunately, the notion of the agency shop was offered to British unions as a solution in quite the wrong context. It certainly failed to find favour with the TUC. This was understandable enough in the circumstances. In the first place it appeared as one of the provisions of the notorious 1971 Industrial Relations Act. The TUC decided to oppose this Act and all its provisions. Second, it was only on offer to "registered unions". The TUC's view was that the other conditions which went along with registration were quite unacceptable and designed to reduce trade union autonomy and influence. TUC policy was that member unions should refuse to register. Virtually all TUC unions observed a Congress decision to this effect. Third, there were additional conditions attached to agency shops which unions found objectionable anyway most notably the balloting and revocation procedures. Yet there is nothing inherently objec tionable in the notion of the agency shop. It was not unknown in Britain before 1971 and a few examples have emerged since 1974. It has a most respectable international pedigree-notably in North American unions. It deals rather well with the difficult and controversial problem of the alleged conscientious objector -who suddenly announces that he objects to paying union subscriptions. In effect such people are informed that they can maintain their objection , but cannot expect to enjoy it free of charge. In this way the agency shop focusses on the main objection which trade unionists have to non- unionists, who work alongside them and enjoy terms and conditions which union organisation alone makes possible. It prevents the existence of 'free riders'. It is worth recalling that it was a Conservative Government that first advanced this device as a reasonable compromise to the problem of the closed shop. Sir Geoffrey Howe, as Mr. Heath's Solicitor General, actually commended it as a practical and reasonable way of reconciling the feelings of 'genuine' conscientious objectors with no less 'genuine' trade unionists who thought there was a common obligation to support the union which bargained on your behalf. He also stressed that if American experience was any guide the agency shop appeared to avoid the need to make any dismissals on grounds of non-unionism. Union membership agreements However, the need for a compromise of this kind disappeared with Labour's return to office in 1974. The Act of 1971 was repealed and a different solution advanced. Labour defined the circumstances in which the law would consider that dismissal on grounds of non-unionism was to be fair in 1974-76. This was where a worker "refused, or proposed to refuse" to belong to a union with a union membership agreement. Such an agree 18 ment would provide that it was the 'practice' for employees of the same class as the dismissed employee to belong to "one of a number of specified independent trade unions". The only exception to be made where individuals could show that they "genuinely object on grounds of religious belief to being a member of any trade union". In these circumstances dismissal was to be "unfair". In many ways the 1974-76 solution worked well enough. Union membership agreements were signed with many employers and they usually provided that an exception should be made for workers with conscientious objections. Indeed, a recent study suggests that in most cases unions agreed to rather wider exceptions than those laid down by law. Often non-unionists already in the employ of a firm covered by a new closed shop were allowed to remain outside the ambit of an agreement. Quite frequently an agreement allowed for conscientious objection on grounds wider than religion. Nevertheless , it can be argued that the move towards written agreements overformalised the closed shop, so that it became more difficult to tolerate the existence of isolated groups of non-unionists in case the existence of the 'practice' was undermined. Difficulties also arose in two related areas. First, as the closed shop advanced to cover non-traditional groups-such as white collar workers in the public sector- there was more chance that workers who had never considered .the possibility were faced with the demand for instant enrolment or the sack. The formal UMAs covering their situation did not always allow this to be regarded as exceptions. Much publicity was given to the odd 'long-standing employee' who refused to join 'on compulsion' and encouraged others to do likewise. Second, from time to time workers who had at first agreed to join, fell out with their local shop stewards, or branch secretary, and sent in their resignation. Others came to consider that the union they had been forced to belong to was not sufficiently active in their interests -in my experience often when the union's leaders were trying to honour the terms of Labour's social contract! Others asked why the union could not ensure their promotion, or obtain their up-grading. At some point they became dissatisfied enough to refuse to pay any further union dues, and were eventually dismissed. By the late 1970s several events of this kind had received much unfavourable publicity. There was the celebrated case of the single chicken sexer, who got to meet Mrs. Thatcher and caused her to weep. There were the five Walsall dinner ladies, who lost their part-time jobs as a result of their refusal to belong to NUPE. Most notorious of all , there were the three members of the staff of BR, who resigned from the NUR and TSSA and were dismissed by their Area Manager. With the support of the Freedom Association they took their case to the European Court at Strasbourg. The issues involved were complex and most of the arguments deployed on both sides need not concern us here. Essentially the railwaymen were arguing that the Labour Government's Act of 1975 was contrary to the European Charter of Human Rights -to which Britain was a party. In effect they were claiming a form of unfair dismissal not permitted under the 1975 Act. Before the case could come before the Court, Labour lost office in the General Election of 1979. As a result the case was presented by the new Conservative Attorney General, although the TUC put in evidence. Some labour lawyers have suggested that the Government failed to argue its case on the best possible grounds at ~ Strasbourg; they allege that if this had been done the decision might not have gone in favour of the railwaymen. Nevertheless, this is what happened, on the basis of a majority verdict. There is also scope for debate about just 19 what was decided at Strasbourg. In particular, the grounds used to justify the decision are capable of interpretation and di agreement. What seems certain is that as it stood the Act of 1975 was found to be too narrow ; the single escape cause of "genuine religious objection" was in need of supplementation. It is also clear that the railwaymen were assisted by the fact that they had all joined the railway service before there was a UMA. Government changes One result of the Strasbourg decision was that the three railwaymen received substantial sums in compensation, far more than they could have obtained under the provisions of the 1975 Act. Another was that their case was much quoted during the passage of the 1980 Employment Act. Indeed Government spokesmen constantly alleged that what they proposed to do in respect of the closed shop was made necessary by the Strasbourg decision. In fact they went much further than that decision implied, and in 1982 another Employment Act went further still. As a consequence the pre ent situation is that UMAs are largely unenforceable at law. The main changes made by the present Government are summarised below. First, the personal grounds on which an employee can claim to remain outside a union within the UMA have been widened. It is now unfair to dismiss anybody who genuinely objects to union membership "on grounds of conscience or other deeply held personal conviction". Second, existing employees who have not at any time been a member of a trade union which is party to a UMA are also excluded; in effect the long-standing non- unionist is protected from the consequences of a new UMA. Third, all existing UMA~ and any further examples of the practice, must now be preceded by an affirmat1ve ballot of the workers affected. 80 per cent of those entitled to vote, or 85 per cent of those who actually vote, must decide in favour of a UMA. Unless there is an affirmative ballot which results in the required majority, dismissal on grounds of non-unionism is unfair. Finally, the Employment Act of 1982 greatly increased the level of compensation which can be claimed for unfair dismissal on grounds of non-unionism, so that at its maximum a payment of more than £30,000 can be awarded. It was also decided that trade unions could be 'joined' in any action for compensation- so that all or part of the sum awarded may need to be found by them. Anew approach How does the focus on collective freedom at work suggest that the problem of the closed shop should be approached in the light of this complex hi tory? Labour must start by restoring the broad balance of the common law position ; workers, like employers, should be free to refuse to cooperate with non-members, or those who refuse to join their association, where they are convinced that to do so would threaten their own bargaining position. On similar grounds I would argue that there should also be a right to refuse to handle the work of non-members. But it does not follow from this that either trade unions or their members should be free to impose a rigid form of closed shop, even where they have not recruited any members and there is no indication that tho e that do belong object to the presence of non-unionists. It should also be possible, within a given clo ed shop area, to allow for the odd conscientious objector, who e presence does not undermine the bargaining po ition of the majority. In my experience very few rank and file trade unionists would want to disagree with any of the above statements, although the best way to embody them in a legal form may well be the subject of debate. 20 My own proposals are five in number. There are three that are essential. First, the right to refuse to work alongside non-unionists, in certain specified circumstances, must be made lawful. In effect workers , through their unions , must be entitled to demand from their employer the recognition of what I would term a Trade Union Employment Area (TUEA) -much as unions were able to demand UMAs under the terms of the 1975 Act, but with rather less formality and with more exceptions and options. Second, within the new TUEAs the conditions of the traditional agency shop should apply. That is to say, those who refused to join , or subsequently resigned , would be offered two alternatives before dismissal was regarded as 'fair' -ie the payment of the equivalent in union dues to the union as a service fee , or payment of a similar sum to be nominated to a charity not connected to any union. (If either option was chosen it would need to be combined with a 'check off' provision-ie payment of the sum required via deduction from the pay-packet by the employer. There would also be no other conditions attached to the agency shop. This time it would not be confined to 'registered' or even 'certified' unions.) Third, in addition to the options of the agency shop, when negotiating new TUEAs, I would favour exempting existing employees who had never belonged to any union , if this was their wish. This is partly because I am convinced that this is necessary for Britain to conform to the substance of the Strasbourg ruling, and I think it is right that we should so do. Also , in a lifetime spent studying the closed shop , I have observed that rank and file trade unionists are quite prepared to make an exception for the odd long-standing 'non' who resents the arrival of the closed shop late in life. They know how to 'draw a circle' round people of this kind , who usually in the end agree to join the union . So I come to two further proposals, where I am uncertain of my ground and open to further argument. The first concerns the position of the 'genuine' religious objector, whose conscientious scruples were respected under the provisions of the 1975 Act. It is arguable that the agency shop deals with this problem, along with those of others who are able to develop less clearly defined and more instantaneous objections to paying union dues. There is much in this argument, but there are a few workers who belong to well-established and long-standing minority sects, such as the Christadelphians. It is arguable that something more should be done to accommodate them. As I understand their position it is that on their reading of St. Paul's epistle to the Corinthians they say they are not allowed directly to support any organisation other than their own Church. I, for one, am prepared to make special somewhat anomalous exceptions in cases of this kind. Once again experience suggests that most rank and file trade unionists would agree. They are usually prepared to be illogical in the interests of tolerance. I am far less certain I would carry all or most trade union activists with me in the case of my final suggestion. This concerns what Labour should do to replace the present balloting provisions for UMAs. It should be obvious that the unjustifiably high percentages required under the 1982 Act are totally unacceptable. In effect they give a veto to a small minority of the labour force. It could also be argued that given the additional qualifications suggested above, notably those provided by the agency shop options, there is no need for a validating ballot in any form . On this argument Labour could reasonably insist on a return to the 1976 position, when trade unions were free to negotiate UMAs whenever it was possible to find an employer willing to agree to them. On the other hand , I have argued above the case for focussing on the rights and freedoms of individual workers, rather than the immunities of their unions. This approach has implications for the right of 21 members to be consulted and to decide things for themselves once they join unions. In chapter five I develop further a number of proposals in the field of internal union government, which would be needed to replace Parts 1 and 2 of the 1984 Act. But it is arguable that a concern for union democracy is important enough to affect the way in which demands are made for the closed shop. In other words, that members at a particular place of work should have a voice in decisions to introduce union membership as a condition of employment; that there should be some indication that they object to the continued presence of non- unionists , and at least see the need for a TUEA. Once this is granted the case for some form of validating ballot reemerges. It is also worth noting that since 1982 there have been 80 or so validating ballots conducted under the very strict conditions of the second Employment Act. The great majority have been won, often with majorities of 90 per cent or more. Yet as far as I am aware they have been undertaken without official union backing since the TUC's position is that unions ought not to co-operate in implementing the existing legislation. For the most part they have been won as a result of the activities of local shop stewards, who knew that they could win, even at the present odds. It is difficult to believe that, if participation in a ballot vote requiring a simple majority were to become official union policy, unions would lose many such ballots. I think this is an option well worth considering. C. Freedom to assemble, communicate and persuade The legal problems in this area mostly arise out of demands for a right to picket. In fact picketing is nowhere defined in the law, but it is commonly understood to involve the activities of workers who attend "at or near premises" connected with a dispute -notably the exits and entrances of the firm or firms involved, Once again the legal complexities surrounding the position of workers and their leaders who appear on the picket line are long-standing, the product ofcommon law decisions and statutory regulation over many years. Unfortunately it is not possible to propose a way through this maze without first describing its main outlines. Attendance at or near a place of work can form the basis for an action for private or public nuisance. Unreasonable obstruction of the highway may be a criminal offence. In practice the main form of control over picketing is exercised by the police. They have power to issue instructions to pickets, which limit their numbers or entirely prohibit their actions if they believe that "a breach of the peace is reasonably anticipated". Any refusal to obey lawful police instructions constitutes obstruction to the police in the exercise of their duties-which is contrary to section 51 of the 1964 Police Act. A limited right to picket was established by the 1906 Act, where the activities complained of were said to be "in contemplation or furtherance of a trade dispute". Picketing was protected for the purpose of communicating information and "peaceful persuasion". Section 15 of the 1974 Act re-enacted these immunities, but removed protection for picketing "at or near a person's residence". The 1980 Act provided an entirely new section 15, which significantly narrowed the scope of protection. With limited exceptions this was now confined to those who picket "at or near their own place of work" with their appropriate union officials. This effectively outlawed both 'secondary' picketing and those forms of 'primary' picketing which consists of workers in dispute who attend at or near their employer's head- office or regional head-quarters. It was designed to make all forms of 'flying pickets' actionable by both the employer 22 concerned and any third party who could claim that their interests had been damaged. The effect is that a striker who strays beyond his own place of work is liable to the full rigour of the usual range of common law torts-notably inducement of breach of contract, intimidation and conspiracy to injure. Even lawful pickets, acting within the scope of the new section 15, are liable for actions for conspiracy to cause loss by unlawful means if, by their express or implied agreement, they are joined by 'secondary' picketers who are not directly involved in their dispute. The limits of justifiable picketing have long been a subject of debate amongst labour lawyers and students of industrial relations. Even where agreement is reached upon what is justifiable it proves to be extremely difficult for those who are in agreement to find the appropriate legal formulation to embody just what they require. In public debate the subject is highly controversial and since the miners' strike extremely political. Few areas of industrial relations are more subject to prejudice, ignorance and misunderstanding. Yet Labour will be expected to say what it intends to do about the present position . Both the unions and Labour's political opponents will want to know exactly where the Party stands. The purposes of picketing My own view is that one must begin by analysing the purposes of picketing. Why do strikers, and their supporters, want to picket at all? Essentially picketing arises out of the need to communicate and persuade during a strike. Its intention is to make the strike effective. It follows that picketing is only necessary if there is no way of doing this without attendance at or near an employer's premises. For example, workers on strike may need to meet each other and their representatives. This may be essential to find out about the employer's latest offer and to take decisions on what to do next. But strikers, or their representatives, may also feel the need to communicate with other workers, whose activities impinge upon the effectiveness of their own actions. There may be reports that other workers are engaged in work that is normally done by strikers or that they are moving goods and delivering supplies which will enable the employer to hold out against consequences of industrial action. In these circumstances picketing will be used in an effort to find out how far this is the case, and whether or not the workers concerned have realised the implications for those who are on strike. In effect the aim will be to present the case for the strikers as they see it; to ask for help and co-operation in the name of 'solidarity'. Obviously if activity of this kind is to be free from liability there must be some kind of right to attend , communicate and peacefully persuade at or near the entrances and exits of firms whose activities affect the dispute. Finally, a dispute may be undermined by the continued presence in the firm of workers who are supposed to be on strike -a minority who voted against the decision to strike, or who refuse to accept a majority decision taken by their representatives. An employer may 'lock-out' or dismiss a group which is demanding recognition or some other objective, and import other workers in their place. This may involve collecting them at their homes and bussing them to work. In circumstances of this sort the aim of picketing is to persuade would-be workers to either join the strike or refuse to take strikers' jobs. In either case the final intention will be the same: to help make the strike effective. It should be clear now why trade union leaders often say that picketing is a sign of weakness; an indication that a strike is not yet fully effective. If all the workers involved withdraw their labour and their presence is important to the employer 23 there is likely to be little need to picket. If workers possess skills which are difficult to replace, and if there is a lively demand for their product or service, an employer's normal reaction to an effective withdrawal of labour is to improve the present offer. A compromise will soon be reached in circumstances of this kind. But picketing may be a necessary response to an employer's ingenuity or resolve. If work can be sub-contracted to other plants, or associated firms , even 100 per cent effectiveness in a particular place of work may make little or no impact. If supplies or materials have been stored , or finished products have been stock-piled, it may be essential to prevent their movement if the employer is to be forced to re-open negotiations. If a previously reasonable employer takes the exceptional step of engaging alternative labour and bussing them to work , picketing may be the only answer. It should also be clear how activities of this kind can lead to demands for a widening of the dispute, and various forms of secondary action against the employer. Workers will naturally form the view that their disagreement with their employer is but the tip of the proverbial iceberg. Once they are defeated, they will say, the same employer, or others in the same industry, will 'take on' other groups. The answer will be seen in terms of 'solidarity now'accompanied by various forms of secondary 'blacking'. What may not be so obvious, to those who have little or no experience of disputes, is just how prolonged and ineffective picketing raises the temperature on picket lines. Few things are more frustrating , after a period out of work , than watching others go through a gate to undermine your strike. Few situations produce more bitterness, or greater guilt. A prolonged and ineffective picket line does not engender an atmosphere in which soft answers turneth away wrath. The limits of peaceful persuasion and non-provocative response are rapidly reached and occasionally over-run. The situation is made worse by the fact that nowadays many workers drive to work in cars, or deliver supplies in huge and inaccessible lorries. The world is divided into those who can see why the atmosphere on a prolonged and ineffective picket line must get worse, and those who feel endless surprise and indignation. The role of the law Yet the law must do all it can to prevent intimidation and violence in situations of this kind, while at the same time recognising the legitimate purposes of picketing. To my mind the problems involved are best considered under four heads: First, the extent to which workers on strike should be free to enlist the help of others directly involved. Second, the area over which picketing should be permitted. Third, the conditions required to make 'peaceful persuasion' a reality under modern conditions. Fourth, what shoud be done when picketers, or others on or around the picket line, seem likely to stray beyond the limits of peaceful persuasion? On the first count I see no justification for limiting the workers' freedom to obtain external assistance while nothing is done to limit the employer's right to act in a similar way. Yet this is just what the 1980 Act demands. Of course, if it were possible to limit the right of multinationals to divert production to another country, or the right of members of an employers' association to fulfill each other's contracts, there might well be a case for limiting the worker's right to ask for help from other trade unionists. But I doubt if this can be done. If it were possible, as has been suggested , for legal limitations to be placed on the right of the employer to import what is traditionally termed 'blackleg' labour, there might well be a case for a similar limitation on the strikers' side. But such a law would be 24 virtually impossible to enforce and would be strongly resented by employers and their organisations. After all, in most cases the most readily available source of substitute labour is supervision. Few employers would want to exchange their right to use foremen to break strikes for the retention of the limitations on secondary picketing contained in the 1980 Act. They would regard this as a very poor bargain. The position is the same in the case of limiting the right to picket to the strikers' own place of work. I do not see how analagous limitations can be enforced on employers. As has been said, the extension of picket boundaries partly arises as a reaction to relative weakness at the place of work, and partly as a response to an employer's ingenuity or resolve. It is unfair and inequitable to penalise and constrict those who are weaker, or facing an ingenious or resolute employer, unless they stray beyond the limits set by the criteria of 'peaceful persuasion' and 'public order' which are considered further below. Within such limits, in my opinion, the right to collective freedom at work suggests that workers should be at least as free as their employer to try to mount an effective response. If, in their opinion, this is thought to involve travelling round the country to picket subsidiaries, or suppliers, or the firm's head office on the day of an important board meeting, I cannot see how a right of this kind can be denied to them on grounds of common equity. So we come to the much more complex question of how the right peacefully to persuade is to be made effective. The view of the judges appears to be that peaceful persuasion must not involve "any kind of constraint or restriction of personal freedom". As Lord Reid has said: " One is familiar with persons at the side of the road signalling to a driver requesting him to stop. It is then for the driver to decide whether he will stop or nor. That. in my l'iew. a picker is emitted to do. If the driver stops the picket can talk to him but only for so long as the driver is willing to listen". 111 It follows that so called 'mass picketing' cannot be used to physically restrain cars or lorries, or the so called 'blackleg bus'. Lord Widgery has maintained that police are entitled to "clear a path" through a crowd of picketers to let out a blackleg bus if they believe that "the rights of the coach driver and the passengers would be interfered with by being forced to stop". In the case in question there was a " reasonable apprehension" that there might be "disorder" or the use of " threatening words or behaviour". In any case, said Lord Widgery , the police have a general duty to regulate the use of the highway and ensure that there is no "obstruction"." The TUC have complained that decisions of this kind have unjustifiably narrowed the right to picket and made peaceful persuasion impossible under modern conditions. They asked the previous Labour Government for "a right for pickets to communicate with the occupants of vehicles so as peacefully to persuade them" . In practice this turned out to be a daunting task, and no legislation was proposed. As V. Craig has observed there are many questions to be decided before a "right to stop vehicles" can be written into the law. Would it be exercised via the police, or by the pickets themselves? Would those approached be under a duty to listen as well as stop, and if so for how long? Would they be immune from further injunctions to stop throughout the course of a given dispute? Or could they be asked to stop again after seven days? Would non-strikers have similar rights to stop those who were on picket duty, and ask them to go to work? It is hard not to agree with Craig when he demands: "... those who propose to give pickers a right to stop must provide answers to these questions before making their 25 proposals. It is flippant to make the proposal and then leave the matter up in the air". 11 My own view is that a right to stop would need to be exercised by the police on behalf of the representatives of workers involved in a given dispute. They would have to decide the reasonable limits of any period of detention, together with its frequency, along lines set out in an agreed Code of Practice. In this respect what I have in mind is not all that different to what many policemen have done in the past but without a legal duty to do so. With their help strikers have been placed in a position where representations can be made to drivers and their passengers. Prior consultation, usually through local trade union officials, has ensured the stopping of vehicles for a short period, for the purposes of peaceful persuasion. Where this has happened problems have only arisen after persuasion has been seen to be manifestly ineffective. But this brings us to the fourth and final question; what should be done if pickets appear to be about to overstep the limits of peacefulpersuasion? My answer to this point is that there caii be no legalisation of action that is clearly intended to intimidate, in the sense of offering threats of violence or physical coercion. So far as I know no reputable trade union has demanded that the law should be changed to grant such a right. The TUC's picketing code stresses that pickets should be advised to "act in a disciplined and peaceful manner even if they are provoked by non-unionists or others". They also say: "It will help to ensure that picketing is peaceful if an experienced member, preferably a union official, is in charge of the picket line. He should have a letter of authority which he can if necessary show to police officers or to workers attempting to cross the picket line. He should ensure that the number of pickets is no larger than is neces 13 sary". Code of Practice After the passage of the 1980 Act the present Government issued a Code of Practice on picketing. It was said to provide a summary of the legal position and "guidance on good practice". Without adding to the law as such the provisions of the Code were to be "admissable in evidence and taken into account in proceedings". For the most part the Code provided a fair summary of the law, while warning employers of ways in which strikers might seek to evade responsibility by "changing the members of the picket line each day". "Large numbers" on a picket line were said to "exacerbate disputes and sour relations". Accordingly , said the Code: "... pickets and their organisers should ensure that in general the number ofpickets does not exceed six at any entrance to a workplace; frequently a smaller number will be appropriate". 14 In introducing the Code to Parliament, Ministers made much of the fact the TUC's Code also referred to the need to ensure that there were no unnecessary pickets, and that their own Code also went on to suggest that union officials should liaise with the police. But for all that there are very significant differences between the two approaches. The TUC Code makes no attempt to impose fixed and absolute terms on the number of pickets. It suggests trade union liaison with the police, rather than the acceptance of quasi-legal responsibilities to ensure that pickets understand the law and the provisions of the Code. It certainly does not propose that union officials should make themselves responsible for enforcing a wide range of limitations on the effectiveness of pickets -including the mainte 26 nance of essential supplies to the employer. Above all, perhaps, the Government Code limits its guidance and the prescription of responsibilities to workers and their representatives. It does not tell employers, or even the police, how they should behave (although it does remind the former of their legal rights) . Throughout the Code it is assumed that reasonability , moderation and discipline need only be taught to strikers and those who aid them. In short, the 1980 Code is designed to widen and reinforce the legal limits imposed by the 1980 Act. It should be repealed , alongside section 16 of that Act. In its place Labour should provide a more equitable Code which sets out in a less one-sided way more balanced guidelines for the preservation of peaceful picketing. It should entourage the maintenance of public order and the avoidance of provocation on all sides. Employers, under such a Code, would be expected to make reasonable provision for peaceful persuasion at or near their place of work. The police would be instructed to co-operate with offical picket leaders, and protect the right to communicate with vehicles. A more general use would be made of sections 9 to 18 of the TUC's Guide to the Conduct of Disputes. In such a context, guidance of the following kind, from paragraph 18 of the TUC Guide, would not be out of place: "In any situation where large numbers of people with strong feelings are involved, there is a danger that things can get out of control particularly in a confined area such as access to a factory. It is therefore particularly important for any such demonstrations to be conducted in a well organised and disciplined manner. It is also important that demonstrations of this kind do not convey the impression that the object is to blockade a workplace".15 D. Freedom to represent and negotiate The final example of a collective freedom which the present Government has undermined is the right to represent fellow workers and to negotiate on their behalf. It should be clear that this does not merely involve the right to join and be active in a trade union. Effective collective action requires an opportunity to approach the employer and state a case on behalf of individuals or groups. At its most developed it involves the right to bargain over pay and other conditions. In broad terms the Tories have left the right to join and be active as it existed under a Labour Government. It remains an unfair dimissal to sack workers because they join and participate in union activities. Indeed, the Government would argue that they have actually added to the penalties that apply to employers who discriminate against union members in sections 3-5 of the 1982 Act. In fact the main purpose of these parts of the Act is to undermine the operation of the closed shop by adding to the compensation for dismissal on grounds of refusing to join a union. But in the interests of 'equity' the Government agreed that the same level of compensation should in principle be made available to workers who can show that they were dismissed for joining, or proposing to join , an independent union. They also left intact section 28 of the 1978 Act, which allowed time off for trade union activities. On the other hand, the 1980 Act repealed virtually all those parts of the Act of 1975 designed to encourage union representation and recognition by the employer. These allowed an independent union to refer a recognition dispute to ACAS. If this remained unresolved , and ACAS recommended in favour of recognition, the union could take a wages and conditions claim to the Central Arbitration Committee (CAC) , which was em 27 powered to make a binding award. It was hoped that the threat of constant reference to the CAC would cause even the most recalcitrant employer to concede recognition. Also repealed was Schedule II of the 1975 Act. This allowed access to the CAC where unions could show an employer did not provide "recognised" terms and conditions or at least the "general level" for similar work in the district. Once again an award in favour of the union was binding on the employer. More recently the Government has also abandoned Britain's long-standing commitment to a 'fair wages' policy for public sector contracts. This sought to ensure that public contractors paid either "recognised" terms or the "general level" in a given industry or trade. In July of this year they announced their intention to remove young workers from the protection of Wages Councils, limiting their functions to the fixing of minimum rates of pay for adults. In their different ways all these institutions and policies were intended by their founders to promote the growth of union membership and the spread of collective bargaining. In this way, it was assumed, the weakest and worst paid sections of the labour force might be. protected and assisted in their struggle to match the natural power of their employer. Past ineffectiveness In practice none of them were fully effective. Pay and job security remained relatively low in the Wages Council trades, and despite the involvement of unions in the wage fixing process the level of organisation has rarely risen above twenty per cent. More recently, as has been said, sections 1 to 16 of the 1975 Act proved a great disappointment, leading to no more than about 4,000 workers a year gaining recognition . Yet long before repeal the CBI was demanding the removal of these sections. The TUC was expressing scepticism and even the ACAS Council told the Government that they were . unworkable. It is worth examining in some detail what went wrong. In their report to the Secretary of State for Employment, ACAS gave three reasons. First, "the absence of criteria" to determine the basis for recognition meant that undue strain was placed on the ACAS tripartite Council. In effect the TUC nominees could not agree with the CBI members on how much support a union needed to be able to demonstrate before ACAS recommended bargaining rights. At the same time the independent members were unable to negotiate a compromise between them. As a result many ACAS recognition reports were vague and inconclusive. Second, in the absence of statutory criteria, the ACAS office tried to make progress by deciding references on an ad hoc basis. But for this to work they had to be allowed to use what they termed an "essential discretion". Unfortunately some employers challenged the right of ACAS officers to act in this way in the courts. The judges decided that in fact they had very little discretion. They needed to find hard evidence of longstanding and stable union membership, rather than a mere 'disposition' to support and join a union ·which has obtained recognition. Finally, when Grunwick objected that ACAS had insufficient evidence to enable it to decide in favour of recognition in their case because the company itself refused to provide the addresses of its employees, the Court decided in favour of the company. From that point it became clear that any determined employer could frustrate the intentions of the law, simply by refusing co-operation. Naturally enough, for its part, the Council concluded that it was unable to "satisfactorily operate the statutory recognition procedures as they stand". and asked to be excused from trying. 28 There is clearly a great deal in each one of these complaints. But in my opinion there were two further defects in the 1975 provisions of equal or greater importance. In the first place they were exclusively concerned with the recognition of trade unions for what might be termed 'full collective bargaining purposes' ie the negotiation of wages and other conditions. There was no reference to the rights of worker-representatives as such. Nothing was done to provide rights of access to the employer which, in certain circumstances, stopped short of the right to bargain over wages and similar matters. I think this narrow emphasis on full bargaining rights for unions , rather than more limited representative rights for their members , helped to maximise employer resistance and contributed to the hostility of CBI nominees on the ACAS Council. They either had to propose the red meat of full-blooded negotiations, or decide against any form of recommendation . Second, the sanctions provided, via a reference to the CAC, turned out to be insufficient and unclear. It was hoped that a mere threat of a reference would cause employers to concede the full right to bargain. Yet in practice the few awards of the CAC on recognition were modest enough. Workers were offered small increases, which were in no way exemplary or punitive. As a result anti-union employers were not unduly worried about the threat of references to the CAC. Of course trade union officials tended to argue at the time that the CAC's awards should have been much more severe. But Parliament gave them no clear statutory instructions to this effect. Indeed, it gave no guidance at all. Lacking a clear authority of this sort, the CAC decided that they had no legal mandate for exemplary sanctions. Finally, the absence of clear criteria, allied to the need for ACAS to investigate all applications, wasted a great deal of time. It also meant that any number of enquired into -even if they only had a handful of members. There was nothing in the legislation to force unions to consider their priorities or areas of primary interest. There was also no way in which the procedure could be said to be helping to rationalise or simplify the problem of union rivalry and membership competition. On the contrary, it was more likely to encourage competitive bidding. As a result ACAS often felt unable to recommend recognition because there were two or three unions squabbling for membership amongst less than twenty per cent of the labour force. Positive rights Two very different questions arise from this catalogue of missed oportunities. First, should a further attempt be made to promote collective freedom by the development of legally based representation and bargaining rights? Second, if so, how can this best be done? I am much more certain I know the answer to the first of these questions than the second, but I will tackle both . There is undoubtedly a need for positive rights in this area. The problem of the recalcitrant employer, who fights the workers' attempts to organise and 'match' his natural power in the labour market, has in no way diminished in recent years. In many ways the climate has become more hostile as the recession and the pressures of international competition have grown in strength. There has certainly been a change since the time when the broadly based Donovan Commission reported unanimously in favour of recognition legislation and an incoming Tory Government introduced proposals to this effect in the 1971 Act. In the first place unemployment is four times as high . The relative strength of the unorganised worker is therefore that unions could ask for their claim to be · much weaker. Secondly, there has 29 emerged a cult of 'macho-management'. A new generation of 'hard-line' production orientated executives has been encouraged to believe that business success, as well as their own promotion prospects, depend on deploying what they are pleased to term their 'right to manage'. (This usually means consulting nobody but themselves before taking irreversible decisions affecting the future employment and well-being of staff.) Third, changes in the composition of the labour force have combined with advances in technology and product demand to produce an increase in the proportion of workers employed in jobs where trade union organisation has always been difficult to sustain eg distribution and the service trades . These have always been characterised by high rates of labour turnover and a great deal of part-time work-much of it done by women. Yet workers in these trades undoubtedly need trade unions at least as much as workers elsewhere. The natural power of the employer is at least as dominant as in large scale manufacture, or the extractive industries, or transport and printing -all areas where trade unions have developed long traditions of collective action and solidarity. Ifanything employer resistance to combination remains more entrenched in distribution and the services -especially among the large number of small and very small shopkeepers who are so near to the Prime Minister's heart. On the other hand, the experience of USDAW suggests that workers in these sectors can sustain and develop union organisation, once they can obtain a measure of recognition and acceptance by the employer. Curiously enough Labour's new programme makes no direct reference to the need to promote the growth of union membership and the spread of collective bargaining. There are certainly no specific proposals to this end. At one point the document says that "our new approach will depend on trade union organisation and a wider scope for joint negotiation and agreement", but this is within the context of proposals for tackling low pay. In this connection there are also pledges to . restore Schedule 11 of the 1975 Act and the fair wages policy for public contracts. In the light of Government's forthcoming attack on Wages Councils the document promises a review of the "whole scope for statutory support for fair wages", but once again the focus is on preventing low pay by minimum wage standards, rather than direct aids to union growth and recognition. I suspect this emphasis partly reflects doubts in Congress House and elsewhere over the efficacy of ACAS activities last time, but it may also merely be that public sector unions, such as NUPE, have been active in pressing their case for minimum wage legislation which affects workers in local government and the NHS. Guiding principles My answer to the second question posed above, is that these parts of Labour's programme are in need of some amplification to make it clear how Labour would attempt to improve on its previous record on union growth and recognition. I would propose that four principles should guide Labour's approach. The first is that, as in the case of other forms of collective freedom at work discussed above, the focus should once again be on workers' rights rather than trade union opportunities. Employers would have a legal obligation to grant the accredited spokesmen of appropriate independent unions certain elementary rights of access -including the right to process grievances on behalf of their members and the right to collect union dues. Rights of this sort would be enforceable at Industrial Tribunals and would need to be accompanied by adequate protection against subsequent victimisation and discrimination ie rights of reinstatement. Employers who had recognised unions would be able to claim that 30 they were already carrying out the intentions of such legislation. But representative rights should not stop there. Given a proven level of support there would be a right to present a claim covering wages and conditions. At this point there would once again be a role for a body like ACAS. This brings me to my second principle. An Act of Parliament would be required to lay down clear criteria governing the level of support required within a given bargaining unit to obtain support for variou degrees of recognition. These should be designed to give workers some help and encouragement whatever level of organisation they had achieved. Yet the degree of help should be related to the degree of support. Needless to ay a body like ACAS would have to be given adequate legal powers to enable them to investigate alleged levels of support. There is scope for reasoned argument about the level and form of upport required to qualify for variou types of assistance. My own view is that indications of support from 30 per cent of the workers in a bargaining unit should be enough to obtain the right to present a wage claim and have it taken seriously. (I believe it is possible to draft a statute that can be made to work with this aim in mind without the problems that aro e in the USA over the need to 'bargain in good faith'.) I also think that once a union can demonstrate that they have majority upport they hould have the right to binding arbitration, if the employer till refu e recognition . If a body such as the CAC finds that this doe not re ult in recognition there ought to be an ultimate right to an 'exemplary award'. Recognition should al o be viewed as an open-ended concept. Employer who have agreed to bargain about wages or conditions hould not be allowed to refu e to bargain about other important matters -uch as closure . My third principle would be that a number of other development , which Labour will naturally want to encourage, should be dealt with in a way which a i ts the spread of rights to represent and negotiate, for example, the restoration of 'fair wages' clau es in government contracts, or the development of Wages Councils and Joint Industrial Councils. In the case of government contracts it would be possible to insi t that would-be contractors should be able to demon trate that they have not refu ed to recognise appropriate trade unions with members in their employ. It would also be worthwhile looking again at a number of neglected proposals of the Donovan Commis ion. They suggested that section 8 of the 1969 Act, under which employers were required to observe " relevant terms and condition " in their industry or trade, should be adapted and applied to areas of low organisation such as the Wages Council industries. They also proposed that compulsory unilateral arbitration hould be available "in indu trie , sections of industry or undertakings" in which the Secretary of State for Employment believe that " it can contribute to the growth or maintenance of some collective bargaining machinery". Industrial democracy I also believe that the early implementation of the EEC Vredeling Directive on a right to information and di closure hould be approached in a way that encourage recognition and the right to bargain. Even the promulgation of the long awaited Fifth Directive on Worker Representation on Management Boards should be looked at from thi point of view. In thi respect A New Partnership: A ew Britain is worth quoting. It ays: "A key feature will be to provideworkers with positive rights to information , consultation and representation in company decisions. The aim will not be 31 to impose any particular model or method, but to widen the collective bargaining agenda beyond wages to crucial investment decisions. We see new rights for workers as a catalyst for the extension of democratic involvement and accountability not just within the enterprise but also beyond it in sector and national planning". These are admirable objectives, although they need to be backed by effective sanctions. It was partly because the last Labour Government came to the conclusion that these could not be achieved without a direct union presence in the boardroom that they decided to establish the Bullock Committee on Industrial Democracy. Bullock proposed the use of existing union machinery to select 'worker director' to sit alongside an equal number of management nominees. However , it will be remembered that the CBI and other management organisations mounted a strong campaign against the implementation of Bullock's majority report and considerable parts of the trade union movement were found to be unenthusiastic or even opposed. The main objections on the trade union side concerned the need to preserve trade union independence in the field of collective bargaining over wages and conditions. As a result very little was done about the Bullock Report by the time Labour left office in 1979. In these circumstances the Party and the TUC are probably wise to make it clear that next time they will not seek to impose the Bullock model , and will try, instead, to develop the range and scope of collective bargaining. All I would want to stress is that the method adopted ought also to encourage the establishment of elementary bargaining rights for those struggling to obtain recognition. A valid criticism of Bullock's proposals, which resulted from their terms of reference , was that they appeared to be exclusively concerned with extending the rights of trade unionists in areas where unions were already well established eg large firms employing more than two thousand workers. Union rivalry So I come to my fourth and final principle, which is easier to state than express in concrete form. I would like to see the statutory machinery for advancing the frontiers of collective freedom fashioned in such a way that it encouraged union co-operation and discouraged union rivalry. I think this would lower the degree of employer resistance and reassure the public. Just as important, I believe it would make it much more likely that union membership would rise significantly in the not so long run. Union rivalry remains the major defect of the British trade union movement. It is much more important -because much more common -than so called undemocratic decisions by unrepresentative union executives. As we have seen in the period from 1974 to 1979 it produced several bitter recognition disputes and led ACAS to refuse a number of important recognition claims. The danger is that a more effective procedure for aiding recognition could merely stimulate and foster a self- defeating growth of union rivalry. The problem is to find an acceptable way of giving expression to this principle. It is impractical to seek to embody in the proposed recognition criteria a plan for the desired direction of union growth alloting various parts of the unorganised labour market to one union after another. Quite apart from the uproar this would cause I am unable to come up with such a plan. Itis equally unrealistic to expect that the TUC will provide one. Ifthe idea were feasible Congress House would have produced a draft years ago. One suggestion , which I advance to start a discussion , is that it should be made 32 clear that ACAS, or its successor, would be charged with the task of avoiding inter-union competition as far as possible. In other words, unions would know that when considering whether or not to grant a union claim , ACAS was more likely to look with favour on single-union applications. In this way, it might be hoped, unions would come to appreciate the advantages of agreeing on areas of recruitment and expansion. Another possibility, which would assist ACAS in carrying out such a task, is that the TUC could be persuaded to operate some sort of sieve procedure. In effect ACAS would refer to the TUC the problem of deciding whether or not a given applicant union was 'appropriate' and 'bona-fide' in respect of a particular recognition claim. As in the case of the application of the TUC's famous Bridling- ton Principles for the avoidance of disputes between member unions, this would not involve the Congress in the formulation of an overall plan. They would remain free to decide each case before them on the basis of the facts as they appeared at the time. But the result should be a gradual reduction in wasteful and self- defeating inter-union competition. E. Freedoms against the employer-a summary This section has been concerned with illustrating how an extension of individual rights is required to develop collective freedom at work. It began by focussing on the need to establish a freedom to withdraw labour collectively free from contractual liability. Ifthis were done, and the definition of a trade dispute suitably widened , unions would be free to resume their proper role as the lawful agents of their members. The second area illustrated the freedom to work with union members only. It was proposed that this right should be restored , but within a legal framework that avoided a rigid form of closed shop. The section then considered the needs of workers for a satisfactory but peaceful right to picket. It was argued that there was no case for imposing restrictions on workers that did not apply to employers. Other than that, the main proposal was for a limited right to stop vehicles. Finally, a number of examples were advanced of how the right to representation and negotiation could be advanced. Once again the focus was on worker rights, rather than trade union immunities. What all these areas of law have in common is that they are mainly concerned with the liabilities and rights of workers and their organisations vis a vis employers, or allegedly injured third parties. Moreover, for the most part--though not entirely -the threat of liability derives from an attempt to plan, carry out, make effective or extend the frontiers of collective action. But, as was suggested in chapter one, these are not the only areas of law which affect trade unions and their members. The 1984 Trade Union Act is centrally directed towards what goes on within trade unions, rather than with their relations with employers or third parties. Each of its three parts is carefully calculated to modify and re-direct the way in which previous statutes and earlier common law decisions have sought to regulate the relationship between unions and members. Of course the Act has wider implications and was designed to influence both industrial relations generally and the financing of the Labour Party. Indeed, in some ways it may be said to be the most ambitious of all three of the Government's attempts to use the law to restrict union freedom. Already it has made a significant impact on how strikes are validated and the likelihood is that it will soon begin to influence the election of union executives. The next chapter considers what the Labour Party should propose to do about its repeal and replacement. 33 5. Freedom within Trade Unions One of the most common misconceptions about trade unions is that until the passage of the present Government's legislation their relations with their members were largely unregulated by law. In fact common law principles of contract and notions of natural justice have long been recognised as applicable to internal union relations, producing a steady flow of case law and an extensive literature on the subject. Moreover, even before 1980 several important statutes were passed which regulated both the relations between unions and their forms of government notably the 1913 Trade Union Act (which dealt with the raising of political funds), and the 1964 Amalgamation Act. It follows from this, unfortunately, that once again a discussion of what Labour ought to do must begin with a summary of the position both before and after the Acts of 1980-84. Common law The basis of common law jurisdiction is that the courts regard a union's rules and constitution as a contract between the members. This means that its terms must be strictly adhered to , and that members have a legal right to any benefits and rights specified in the rules -eg in relation to union elections and participation in union government. They also cannot be disciplined or expelled in ways not provided for under the rules and the courts will interpret any general expulsion rules in a limited way in the interests of the individual member. This oversight of union rules I have elsewhere termed "the authorisation principle" . It is intended to ensure that before any union leader or executive acts they are able to cite a rule which authorises them to do so. But the over-sight of the common law does not stop at this point. All domestic tribunals, such as the executive committee of the union when considering cases of disciplinary action, must observe what lawyers term the "principles of natural justice". These entail the need to act in a fair and quasi-judicial way , which the Americans rather appropriately term a respect for "due process". In the case of unions this involves, amongst other things, informing members in advance of any charges against them ; allowing them an opportunity to state their case etc. In addition , since expulsion from a union may affect a person's ability to earn a living, the courts take the view that unions must 'refrain from arbitary behaviour' in dealing with their members' rights and interests. Some legal commentators have argued that in applying the principle of authorisation and natural justice the courts have over-stressed the rights of the individual at the cost of "the industrial relations merits". 16 It has been suggested that decisions and even expulsions have been 34 regarded as unlawful where the worst that has happened has been that the union in question has misread a minor clause in its rule book, or cited the wrong subparagraph. It has also been argued that on occasions judges have expected too much from laymen , who may not be fully aware of how earlier judges have interpreted the more arcane requirements of natural justice. Be that as it may, it cannot be contested that for some time now both principles have been applied with considerable strictness to internal trade union activities. And since the case of Bonsor, in 1956, those who can demonstrate that they have been unlawfully harmed by their union, in defiance ofeither principle, have been able to obtain compensation in the form of civil damages. The1980Act What changes and additional forms of liability have been grafted on to common law liability as a result of recent legislation? We must begin with the Act of 1980. This sought to establish protection against "unreasonable exclusion or expulsion" where there was a union membership agreement in operation ie it was intended to provide extra protection against arbitrary action within a closed shop area. Complaints are heard by Industrial Tribunals in the first instance, with a right of appeal to the Employment Appeal Tribunal on an issue of law. Compensation is fixed on a scale related to unfair dismissal compensation. It was never possible to obtain from Government spokesmen, during the pas sage of the 1980 Act, how far they took the view that sections 4 and 5 of the Act were likely to add significantly to the rights of union members at common law. Clearly there was a right of 'exclusion' as well as 'expulsion'-which meant that under the statute a would-be union member could complain of a refusal to allow entry into a union operating a pre-entry closed shop. The common law has not so far recognised a right to join any vocational association -either a trade union or a professional association. So that in this area at least an additional jurisdiction was created. What was made clear was the likely meaning to be attached to the term 'unreasonable' -both in respect of exclusion and expulsion cases. In the case of the former would it include a refusal to admit on grounds of high unemployment among existing members? In the case of the latter could it exten·d beyond the existing bounds set by the authorisation principle and natural justice? These questions were never answered and no guidance was given by the Act. Since 1980 it appears that very little use has been made of sections 4 and 5, which is not surprising in the light of what the Act of 1982 did to the closed shop. As a result the position is still unclear. The 1984 Act The next Act to affect internal union relations directly was that of 1984. As has been said, each part of this measure added very significantly to the degree of statutory control. Part 1 imposed periodic, universal direct balloting on all unions for the purpose of electing their "principal executive committee". All forms of indirect election were rendered unlawful and the presumption is that voting will be by postal ballot. Workplace ballots are permitted if a union is satisfied that it can meet the stringent conditions laid down for postal ballots under section 2 of the Act -eg secrecy, fair and accurate counting, and an up to date and comprehensive register. Part 2 of 1984 required similarly stringent and universal ballots before official strike action. It specified in considerable detail the question to be posed on the voting paper, including the fact that given 35 the present state of the law , as we saw in chapter two , any collective action is likely to involve the worker " in a breach of his contract of employment". This subsection has been rightly termed the 'intimidation cl._ause'. Securing an affirmative majority obtains the right to use lawful strike' action, but only if the strike is called within four weeks of the ballot. Part 3 of 1984 dealt with political funds. It amended the 1913 Trade Union Act, which set aside the effects of the notorious Osborne judgment of 1910. In the Osborne case the House of Lords decided that trade unions were not allowed to use any of their existing funds for so called political purposes-most notably financing and sponsoring Members of Parliament. The 1913 Act, a compromise obtained by the infant Labour Party from the Liberal Government of the day , allowed unions to spend money on political objectives where they had conducted a ballot of their members which favoured the establishment of a separate political fund . It also defined what was to count as 'political' and stipulated that such activities could only be financed from a fund established for this purpose. Part 3 of 1984 restricts the operation of the 1913 Act in three ways. First, ballots to establish or continue a political fund must be undertaken and won every ten years. Second, the criteria to be observed in running them are made to conform to those stipulated in Parts 1 and 2 of the Act, Third , the definition of what is to count as 'political' is significantly widened. It now appears to cover such activities as campaigns by a union like NALGO , which is not affiliated to the Labour Party and has no political funds , against reductions in social services and rate capping. Union democracy As in previous sections, it is best to begin by deciding what Labour should do about the present position by asking why unions require rules, constitutions and committees to take decisions on behalf of their members. The short answer is because · combination , to be effective, requires order and solidarity and a respect for collective decisions. Ifcollective bargaining is successfully to replace individual bargaining there must be a procedure for arriving at common policies. So far as it is possible members must have an opportunity to participate in decisions which they may be required to put into effect -in the last analysis by withdrawing their labour. Yet all the responses of unions , and all their administrative decisions, cannot be preceded by debate and agreement. There has to be a role for leadership -not least while a dispute is in progress and the employer is making a series of final offers which have to be assessed and judged. But if leadership is to be followed and trusted , it must emerge as the result of some process of participation -the most obvious of which is some form of election. It can thus be argued that the main function of union rules and constitutions is to foster participation and membership involvement in policy determination and leadership selection. Unless this is done , and done effectively, unions are unlikely to be able to commit their members to collective action. In this sense democracy in trade unions is not a luxury, or an opportunity for personal expression. It is the necessary price paid for unity and solidarity. Reservations However, three reservations need to be entered at this point. First, solidarity is difficult to come by and unity is never complete. There are always differences between members about what they want and who they wish to lead them . Members have different priorities according to their 36 age, skill, occupation, traditions and attitudes to collective action. It follows that there are always minorities willing to complain about what leaders do in their name, or what majorities decide should be done. Sometimes minorities or individuals take their differences to the point where they refuse to obey properly authorised leaders who are carrying out majority decisions. Given the commitment to collective action and the importance of preserving majority rule this gives rise to the problem of union sanctions and union discipline. Unions must have sanctions of some kind , but they are almost always extremely reluctant to use them . Second, the manufacture of commitment and solidarity in different unions cannot be ensured by a single participative model. Like firms, or political parties, or London clubs, or University Senates, or the Inns of Court, unions develop their own constitutional arrangments for determining policy and selecting leaders. Those who study them with any degree of sympathy or understanding usually revel in their wide diversity of arrangments for taking essentially similar decisions. Where they are small or occupationally homogeneous, they tend to rely on direct methods of election; unless they give special emphasis to the role of their annual conference. Where they are unusually large and heterogeneous they invariably 'mix' direct systems of election with indirect systems. This is thought to be more flexible and to further future amalgamations and mergers. Students of industrial relations-including the present writer -have written long and boring books about the factors which influence and determine the structure and government of different unions. Fortunately they need not concern us here. All we need to note is that, as in so many walks of life, what is required is what works. Third, because of the organisational importance of participation to trade unions , they need to be far more democratic than most other organisations in modern society. Firms, especially large and powerful firms, can afford to be far more authoritarian and bureaucratic as one moves upwards towards the boardroom. Boards of directors hardly ever take votes and regularly re-elect each other. Shareholder control is usually a mockery and annual general meetings are almost invariably rubber stamps-unless the company has had a disastrous year, or it is threatened with a take-over bid. Itis much the same with professional bodies, trade associations and in most organised religions. These admirable public institutions are for the most part organised on the basis of recognised levels of hierarchy and accepted degrees of distinction. They never have to call on their members for united action which could result in dismissal. Most of their leaders would have a hard time controlling the average union branch , let alone a hostile factory meeting. They have hardly ever heard of Citrine's ABC of Chairmanship-essential reading for any union official facing a rank and file revolt. Nevertheless, trade union democracy is sometimes a wilting and sickly bloom. The problem is apathy and access to members. Unless workers can be contacted at the place of work during working hours few are prepared to turn out for routine branch meetings. Of course, those who are unusually active will , by definition , turn up more regularly. Many of them will be more 'militant' than those who stay away , although they may be unwilling to take on the hardest work. In any case, all the indications are that nowadays the 'militant' few cannot commit the more moderate but absent majority to any sustained form of action which they do not support. And in the present climate sustained action is required to move employers. Partly for this reason, as Undy and Martin show in their recent study, there has been a steady growth of more direct methods of securing participation in decisions likely to result in strike action. This 37 pre-dates the coming into effect of Part 2 of the 1984 Act. It includes an increasing use of secret ballots. Leaders who have sought to go against this trend have been rejected and humbled-though they have not always been prepared to admit it. 17 The law and union government What conclusions may be drawn about the role of the law in relation to union government from the above analysis? What are the implications for the repeal or reform of exising legislation and the modification of common law liability? Four points can be made. First, if the law is to perform a useful and constructive role it should be designed to help trade unionists themselves with two complementary aims in mind : (a) to improve opportunities for involvement and participation in union decisions; (b) to safeguard individual membership rights under existing constitutions and rules. All the evidence suggests that the first of these aims is best advanced by promoting and protecting membership rights at the place of work. At the very least, there must be a right to hold meetings and a right to organise and participate in elections on employers' premises. Those who are genuine in their expressed regard for the state of union democracy must favour rights of this kind. It is the primary test of their sincerity. During the passage of the 1984 Act this point was made over and over again from Opposition benches, but without making much impact on Government spokesmen. They were taken up with their ever more rigid model of democracy; with fastening duties and liabilities on union officials. They were mainly concerned to threaten unions with endless legal wrangles, and constant re-elections , whenever it was not possible to show that an impractical and unvarying system of plebiscite democracy had been carried out to the letter. It is true that when it was clearly demonstrated to them that workplace ballots produced much higher turnouts , the Government were eventually prevailed upon to allow balloting at the place of work. But they continued to insist on the same stringent conditions as those laid down in their 1984 'postal model' and refused to agree to a proper framework of complimentary obligations to be imposed on employers. It is also true that back in 1980, as part of the scheme to promote the use of ballots by providing a subsidy, Ministers agreed to provide that unions could "request" employers to grant them "a convenient opportunity" to conduct such a ballot and that section 2(1) of the 1980 Act went on to stipulate that " the employer shall , so far is reasonably practical, comply with that request". But it is far from clear how far this right extends, or what is is worth, or how it can be enforced. It also does not cover election meetings , or procedures for the nomination of candidates. Nothing is provided to deal with other kinds of trade union decisions eg those that clearly do not involve secret ballots in the terms of the 1980 Act. What Labour must provide is a more extensive and balanced framework of participative rights, which fully recognises the extent to which union democracy depends on adequate workplace facilities. This would need to go far beyond the 1975 ACAS Code of Practice, which only deals with time off for trade union duties. It essentially concerns the 'industrial relations' activities of union officials, such as shop stewards. It does not provide general facilities for union members. Of course, although adequate facilities for contacting members and involving them in union government usually involves workplace rights this does not mean that Labour's legislation in this field should discriminate against other forms of membership contact. Some unions prefer to use postal ballots to deal with major election contest. For this reason Labour should also pro 38 vide a right to 'freepost' facilities. Yet experience of recent political fund ballots, imposed under the recent restrictive provisions of the 1984 Act, suggests that , offered the chance, the great majority of unions prefer 'mixed' systems of participation. In other words, workplace ballots where large branches are organised on a workplace basis, and postal ballots for scattered sections of the membership organised in general or area based branches. In this way very high levels of · participation were obtained in -recent political ballots-although tqe results did not please Labour's opponeqts. The second point to emphasise is that within a balanced legal frame}Vork there is no justification for many of tpe petty and meaningless restrictions imposed by the 1984 Act. For example, no good reason has ever been given for the total ban on· 'indirect' elections to union executives. Government spokesmen were totally unable to even explain why they were insisting on this bizarre and unique condition in 1984. They never even sought to suggest that the indirectly elected executive members of APEX, or,the GMBATU, or NALGO, were less responsible, or more unrepresentative, or of a lower standard, than other directly elected members in the same or different unions. When asked why it was that indirect elections were still thought to be appropriate for the Law Society or Unilever, but not for the TGWU, Government spokesmen took offence. Similar considerations tell against an exclusive reliance on official strike ballots to validate strikes. As embodied in Part 2 of 1984, this resembles nothing so much as the system of mass plebiscites favoured in the early days of the Third Reich. Membership participation is viewed as a right to answer simple questions with an unqualified 'yes' or 'no'. There is no notion of a developed and discursive democracy , where there is room for delegated responsibility and reporting back. Nobody is supposed to move amendments, or adv ance counter-proposals. Yet once again this primitive system is not to be imposed on the BMA, or the Conservative Party Conference, which never has binding votes anyway. Only trade unions are to be placed within the confines of this rigid and intimidatory system. Of course it is not suggested that Labour should seek to discourage strike ballots in any form. On the contrary, as was explained above, the present trend is towards direct methods of participation- partly because of the size of many modern bargaining units, and partly because of the uncertain conditions of the mid-1980s. Part 2 of 1984 has, it is true, given a further impetus to this development-especially since . a number of employers have threatened legal action unless ballots have been held within the terms of 1984. But all .J.-abaur needs to do is to encourage and facilitate the widest possible range of participative methods: workplace meetings and secret ballots; representative conferences in addition to direct consultation with members. Once again , what should be .encouraged is what works and in the last analysis the best people to decide the appropriate 'mix' must surely be trade union members themselves. To be fair it must be admitted that in the case of strike ballots the Conservatives were not totally without arguments. They simply asserted that they happened to know that secret ballots were more demo cratic than shop floor meetings , because the latter were invariably 'rigged' and subject to intimidation. Naturally enough no evidence was adduced to prove this since none exists. Instead reference was made to occasional television news items, where mass meetings appeared to be followed by what looked like a confused and indeterminate show of hands. Unsubstantiated allegations of this kind .do not constitute a convincing case against all forms of decision taking which do not conform with Part 2 of 1984. On the contrary, it has been my experience that properly conducted meetings at the place 39 of work can be an equally valid way of deciding whether or not to use industrial action . The decisions that emerge as a result can be far more reliable and produce a greater sense of unity and commitment. Where conditions are appropriate they should be encouraged and facilitated . But this means that it must be possible for all the workers involved to attend. There must also be adequate time for discussion and debate before a final vote. Of course, in any system of decision taking so far invented, there remains a risk of manipulation, or even intimidation. (To judge from recent leaks such things are not unknown in the Cabinet.) But in the case of trade unions it is possible to deal with these potential blemishes without insisting on mandatory ballots, backed by the threat of a loss of immunities. Which brings me to my third point. Democratic guidelines While it is foolish and unjustifiable to seek to impose on all unions the same rigid model of plebiscite democracy, it does not follow that there is no case for trying to ensure the observance of certain well- established democratic principles. Indeed , my view is that once unions are assured of an adequate framework of participative rights at the place of work, they ought to have no objection to this. What is required is agreement on a set of 'democratic guidelines', or 'minimum rule book standards'. These should be discussed and agreed with the TUC before the introduction of a bill embodying statutory participative rights at the place of work. They could then be embodied in a Code of Practice, which would be taken into account in deciding how far individual unions were entitled to enforce their new rights. In general terms unions would have to show that their internal decision- making processes measured up to stan dards set out in the Code of Practice. This should provide both an incentive and the means to improve democratic practices. The contents of such a Code of Practice would mainly concern union rules and regulations affecting elections, workplace representation and the use of industrial action. But there is no good reason why other subjects should not be covered. In a pamphlet of this length I can do no more than indicate the kind of standards I myself would favour. In the case of union elections the Code might provide that the procedures for nomination and voting should be 'fair' and conducive to accuracy. Members of a given executive should emerge as the result of a process of individual voting- either by means of direct participation , or by a 'mix' of direct and indirect methods. One result of guidelines of this kind would be the elimination of practices like branch block voting -where those who attend can commit the entire vote of the branch to the candidate they favour . In the case of the use of industrial action the criteria would need to be rather more complex, but once again I would want to favour and encourage individual voting -either by postal or workplace ballot, or after properly regulated shop floor meetings. However , no system of guidelines should rule out a proper role for delegate meetings and representative gatherings especially in the formulation of policy options. Membership rights Finally, the notion of a Code of Practice also has a contribution to make when considering what Labour should do about the second aim of the law in relation to union government as specified above-ie its role in upholding membership rights. Here I would propose the repeal of those sections of the 1980 Act dealing with "unreasonable exclusion and expulsion" 40 and the transfer of all questions involving individual membership rights to Industrial Tribunals, with a right of appeal to the Employment Appeal Tribunal. It seems to me that the tripartite and well- established Industrial Tribunals already have a relatively good record in dealing with the rights of individual workers against the employer in respect of unfair dismissal , or discrimination on grounds of sex or race. They would seem to be the natural bodies to deal with claims by workers against trade unions themselves. Of course before this could be done the Tribunals would need to be provided with appropriate legal criteria to govern their decisions. I would draw these from the more sensible and practical decisions of judges when applying the authorisation principle and the rules of natural JUStice. I would also have regard to the contents of the Code of Participation Practice and its minimum rule book standards. The Code itself would contain guidance on how to bring union rules and practices into conformity with the new standards. It would also tell union members what their rights were. To summarise all that is proposed in this section so far: First, in the place of a rigid and limited set of restrictions and liabilities, there should be an agreed Code of Participative Practice, designed to encourage unions to extend and develop their ways of involving the majority of members in important decisions. Second, unions require a complementary and balanced framework of parttctpattve rights against the employer at the place of work , designed to assist unions who agree to observe the new Code of Participative Practice. Third , a more effective and acceptable machinery for protecting the rights of union members agamst thetr union -especially in areas such as discipline, expulsion and the use and conduct of elections. Political activity I turn finally to what needs to be done about Part 3 of 1984 ie that part which redefined political activity and made it necessary for all unions who wanted to maintain a political fund to conduct a fresh ballot. My own view is simple enough. Having denounced this as an unnecessarily partisan measure, which imposed unfair restrictions on unions that did not apply to employers or corporations, 1 am content to leave it where it stands on the statute book. The fact is that this measure has back-fired on the Government. So far all unions who wished to do so have secured a majority in favour of a ballot for political purposes. They have then used it to remain affiliated to the Labour Party. All I would propose is that a similar provision should be enacted by Labour which applies to corporate bodies of all kinds. Before subscribing to the Conservative Party they too should be under a similar legal obligation to conduct a ballot of their shareholders, to gain the right to establish a separate political fund along the lines of the 1913 Act. Individual shareholders would be entitled to contract out. Those who decided not to do so would know that their rate of return on dividends would be adversely affected. Ian Mikardo has long had such a bill in his pocket, I consider that one of ~abour's first acts should be to mtroduce a btll along the lines of Mikardo's measure. I do not see how there could be any legitimate objection by the Tories, and it would only serve them right. 41 6. Freedom at Work and Community Interests So far this pamphlet has been concerned with the re-establishment of collective freedom at work. But it would be idle to ignore the fact that all forms of freedom can restrict and even damage other interests, including those ofthe community as a whole. In the case ofunions it is often claimed that their attempt to match the power of employers in the labour market results in unjustifiable damage to the commi.mity in two main ways. First, by causing, or adding to, the forces of cost-induced inflation, with unfortunate consequences for Britain's efficiency, competitiveness and level of employment. Second, by interrupting or denying the public essential services during prolonged and widespread disputes, producing hardship and inconvenience to innocent members of the public. Thi pamphlet is not basically concerned with what Labour should do about inflation, investment, employment or the rate of growth. These matters are discussed in A New Partnership: A New Britain and other policy document . Other writers, with various degrees of knowledge and ho tility, have written at length about the role of trade unions and wage bargaining in facilitating, or hindering, economic welfare. evertheless, it eem to me that at this point it is desirable for me to say a word or two about my own attitude to these matters. Incomes policy Without sub cribing to the extreme and ill documented exaggerations of free market economists like von Hayek or Minford , I believe that m the past escalating pay \cttlement have contributed to Britain 's economic problems. I am also convmced that if Labour' plans for sustained growth leading to higher employment levels are to be carried out, there will be a need for what used to be termed some kind of pay policy. I also believe that if the electorate is not convinced that Neil Kinnock and his colleagues are ufficiently aware of the dangers of runaway inflation as the level of output ri e , they will not be able to maximise upport for the kind of program- me to re tore collective rights which is outlined here. Yet what follows is in no way a blue-print for another experiment in incomes policy, designed to fit the circumstances of an as yet unknown period of Labour rule. It is more a personal and brief comment on some of the inevitable problem , piu an attempt to draw one or two lessons from things that have happened since the winter of 1979. Three poinh can be made. Fir t, there must be no attempt next time to concentrate the entire credibility of the policy on the attainment of a s1mple, near 42 universal , norm for pay increases-eg 5 per cent, 10 per cent or £6 plus 'selffinanced productivity pay'. In the case of the private sector the varying fortunes of companies in different product and labour markets since 1979 has made such an approach inappropriate. Firms who are now doing relatively well, or who face some labour shortages, would not observe such norms -unless they were fixed at levels which would ruin less profitable firms , where workers may still face the prospect of redundancy, or closure. It follows that the next Labour Government must be willing to tolerate a continuing variation in settlement levels, which will be more closely related to so called 'market factors' than was the case last time. What it should seek to avoid is a general escalation of earnings, which gathers growing force as employment expands until it endangers the Government's plans for the economy as a whole. Second, the problem of pay in the public sector will be much more urgent and pressing next time. During the last three rounds public sector pay increases have generally been lower than those in the private sector -unless the workers involved were favourites of the Prime Minister, or blessed with long-standing pay formulas. They have also been more unevenly distributed. The police, the army, the judges and the firemen have all done relatively well. Manual workers in local government and the NHS, along with teachers and social service workers, have been relentlessly squeezed. Civil servants, nurses and water-workers have enjoyed both good years and bad years. As a result there has been a massive disturbance of traditional differentials within a significant but uneven reduction in real wages. The danger is that Labour will be expected to remedy all these defects within months of taking office. What it will need before that date will be a well-thought out and realistic policy for pay thoughout the public service sector, agreed at Cabinet level. This will almost certainly involve the reintroduction of some kind of Comparability Commission, to help decide how best to distribute the limited sums available during the first few years of office. Third, as a result of both these developments, Labour's Economic Summit will need to take a rather different form than any established in the past. It should mainly focus on providing the material for a much more continuous and realistic ettlement of how the various indexes of economic activity are moving and affecting each other. What the Government should stress, from the outset, is its readiness to adjust its plans to deal with any significant departures from target. The trouble in the past has been that the rigidity of Treasury calculations, plus Ministerial reluctance to admit to mistakes, has severely inhibited this process of adjustment. It has usually been found necessary to fix , in some form of financial concrete, public expenditure, investn:._;it and growth targets for at least a year at a time -long before it was possible to decide how pay was likely to move, or its likely impact on prices. As a result unreal assumptions have been allowed to persist concerning what could be done to restrain or limit pay settlements. In 1979 this led to the inevitable collapse of the formal targets of incomes policy. It was rigidities of this kind, plus Ministerial obduracy at the highest level , which paved the way to Labour's last 'Winter of Discontent'. One advantage of a different and more flexible approach should be that next time there will be no need for a detailed agreement on a given level of pay increase to be applied each year across the economy. No social contract, or statement of intent, to be launched at yet another NEDO press conference. All that needs to be demonstrated , in action when the time comes, is a willingness to respond to intiatives and options posed by Govern ment. 43 Strikes in essential services On the question of strikes in essential services the problem is that at the moment of writing it is not known what the present Government will propose. There was a pledge to introduce legislation on this matter in the 1979 Conservative election manifesto, and it may well be that a more detailed announcement will be made sometime next year. But so far the only serious discussion of the question from the Conservative view is that contained in the Prior Green Paper, Trade Union lmmunities. This prepared ground for the 1982 Employment Bill, but nothing was proposed in that Bill to curtail the right to strike in essential services. Indeed, the Green Paper itself was vague and discouraging on the subject and tended to stress the difficulties involved. It is true that the powers taken under the 1971 Act to impose statutory cooling- off periods and a strike ballot were discussed at length -including the disastrous and isolated attempt to use this part of the 1971 Act during the 1972 rail dispute. But no attempt was made to draw any lessons from this experience. Also briefly reviewed was the similarly discouraging record of the American Government, when using Taft-Hartley provisions to impose cooling-off periods and compulsory ballots in essential services. It was pointed out that trade unionists have usually obeyed such orders to return to work , but have almost invariably voted for a strike after the cooling-off period. As a result this part of the Taft-Hartley Act is now largely unused. After describing the evident " lack of success of cooling-off periods" the Green Paper went to to consider a number of "alternative approaches" -including passing laws to make it unlawful for certain " key groups" to strike. The only examples of this in Britain at the moment occur in the armed forces , the police and when merchant seamen are at sea. But, as the Green Paper says, in each of these instances "there are arguments of public order, security and safety which make if difficult to draw any general lessons from other industries". Understandably enough the writer of the Green Paper concluded: "It is possible to argue that the most effective way ofmaking progress on this question is through voluntary 'no strike' agreements between management and unions in those sectors of industry where strikes threaten the national interest" .'" This seems to me to be only common sense; but it is not difficult to see why the suggestion has not been taken any further in the last four years. Since Prior's period at the Department of Employment the climate has hardened against proceeding by agreement in matters of this sort. In any case a voluntary agreement to avoid strikes would have to provide the unions involved with an acceptable alternative way of resolving outstanding differences. There has only ever been one alternative on offer -genuinely independent and binding arbitration. Since Prior's banish~ ment the Thatcher Government has come to oppose arbitration in all its forms-not least for public service workers employed in essential services. The Prime Minister is convinced that arbitration is inflationary and thinks it represents an abandonment of management's responsibilities. No strike agreements This is an ill-informed and biased judgement , with the usual lack of supporting evidence. [t seems to me that there is a case for taking a lead in the public sector to reduce the likelihood of damaging strikes, although this need not involve legislation. I would like to see Labour take the lead in this area. My proposals would be four in number. First, the Government 44 should offer all trade unions in the public service sector the option of an ex parte arbitration agreement on pay and conditions disputes. This would mean that either party could take outstanding disagreements to an independent panel of neutrals selected by the unions and management. Both sides would agree to be bound by their decisions. It follows that for the period of any such agreement there would exist, for the service in question, a voluntary 'no strike' agreement. But this would be the result of negotiation and consent. It would have nothing to do with the law. Second, for the rest of the public sector, eg in the case of the nationalised industries, it would be Government policy to encourage employers there to offer similar facilities to the unions they recognise. But this would be a matter for the management and unions of each industry; no pressure would be placed on them by Government. Third, in the private sector generally, ACAS would be asked to facilitate and encourage the development of all types of third-party dispute resolution -ie conciliation, mediation and even arbitration. Once again no pressure would be placed on either side of industry to agree to formal 'no strike' agreements. Finally, as was mentioned above in the section on trade union recognition, and as the Donovan Commission also proposed, compulsory unilateral arbitration would be made available " in industries, sections of industry or undertakings" where the Government believed that it could "contribute to the growth or maintenance of collective bargaining machinery". In this way, the hope would be, both sides come to accept that there were often better ways of dealing with problems than long and protracted strikes. 7. Summary and Conclusions The Prime Minister maintains that there is no workable alternative to her policies for economic survival; more cuts in public expenditure, further reductions in the size of the public sector and the responsibilities of government, the removal of all remaining restrictions and the operation of 'market forces'. Attacks on trade unions have always been an essential part of her ideology. Thus it has become customary to assert, dence, that the legal 'immunities' of without any respectable supporting evi-British un ions have been the main cause of 45 higher prices, reduced employment and the inability of British business to compete. In the name of reducing union power laws have been passed and action has been taken which has already severely restricted individual and collective rights at work. Already the position in Britain compares badly with that which exists in most other advanced democracies where they have managed to combine greater freedom at work with much higher standards of living and lower levels of unemployment. Yet the Government is preparing further attacks. They have not yet finished with trade unions or their members. However, there are signs of a growing disillusion with the consequences of the Government's obsession with free-market economics. It is hard to see what it has achieved ; apart from lower levels of employment, a reduced manufacturing base, an impoverished welfare state and a much more unequal society. There is also an increasing readiness to consider a more complex and less divisive approach. The broad outlines of such a policy, based on public intervention, public investment and a more co-operative approach to both sides of industry, has been outlined in Labour's recent policy document: A New Partnership: A New Britain. Central to its approach is a constructive and useful role for trade unions and their members. To this end Labour is committed to repeal 'divisive' Tory laws. But it has not, as yet, worked out what it will put in their place. The central aim of this pamphlet is to contribute to the debate which must now begin on the shape and content of Labour's alternative framework. The electorate will want to know the broad direction that is proposed. It is also essential to gain general agreement within the movement and to avoid unproductive approaches. Collective freedom at work The main suggestion advanced is that the focus should be on restoring and extending freedom at work -including, above all, the right to act collectively. But the argument should be about the need for worker rights, rather than the creation of additional 'immunities' for trade unions. Four examples were advanced of how the restoration of collective freedom might be achieved. The first concerned the freedom to withdraw labour collectively. Here what needs to be done is obvious enough. Workers must be able to act in concert, without the risk of action for breach of contract. Once this is ensured unions can resume their rightful role as the lawful agents of their members, enjoying rights no more singular than those accorded to unions in other democratic countries. The second example chosen concerned the freedom to work with trade unionists only. The proposal advanced was that the broad balance of the common law position should be restored. Workers, like employers, should be free to refuse to co-operate with non-members, where they are convinced that this is necessary to protect their trading interests. But it does not follow that either unions or their members should be free to impose a rigid closed shop. Trade unions must be prepared to be illogical in the interests of tolerance. The third example related to the right to picket. It was decided that there can be no justification for limiting the workers' right to try to obtain external help, while limiting the right of employers to act in a similar way. It is also clear, in contemporary circumstances, that the right peacefully to persuade cannot be effective without a limited and controlled 'right to stop vehicles'. But nothing should be countenanced which is any way intended to encourage or licence intimidation. The final illustration of collective free 46 dom at work concerned the right to represent and negotiate. It was argued that there can be no doubt of the need for positive rights in this area. It follows that Labour must try harder than last time to find effective ways of encouraging union growth and the spread of collective bargaining. Once again the focus should be on adding to worker rights rather than trade union opportunities. Some help and encouragement should be available whatever the level of organisation. Yet the degree of help on offer should be graduated, and related to the degree of support that already exists. There must also be adequate powers to prevent employers from sabotaging the work of bodies like ACAS and the CAC. Freedom within trade unions All four examples above concern the liabilities and rights of workers in relation to employers and/or third parties. But there is also the question of internal union relations and the role of the law in protecting freedom within unions. The pamphlet argued that if the law is to perform a constructive role here it must be designed: (a) to improve opportunities for the involvement of members in union decisions; (b) to safeguard individual membership rights. Tory legislation fails in both respects because it seeks to impose impractical and unjustified legal restrictions and does not impose complementary obligations on employers. What is required is an agreed Code of Participative Practice, plus a complementary framework of rights against employers at the place of work. Part 3 of the 1984 Act can be left as it is. It needs only to be complemented by similar provisions governing political donations for corporate bodies. Freedom at work and community interests All forms of freedom may restrict and damage other interests, including those of the community as a whole. Without subscribing to the extreme and unsubstantiated exaggeration of the free-market economists, it is clear that in the past escalating pay settlements have contributed to the problem of cost inflation. More recently, protracted and bitter disputes in essential services have led to widespread public inconvenience. It follows that Labour should be prepared to complement its programme for restoring and extending freedom at work with policies designed to tackle both these problems. On the first of these issues three points were made. First, the need to get away from rigid and near-universal pay norms, which are no longer practical or required; what needs to be avoided is a rapid and general escalation of earnings which rises to a point where it endangers plans for the economy as a whole. Second, the importance, next time, of developing consistent and realistic policies for pay in the public service sector. Third, the need for government to adopt more flexible economic targets, which can be adjusted in the li ght of pay movements as they emerge. On the second it was proposed that Labour should encourage the adoption of ex parle arbitration agreements. If accepted they would amount to no strike agreements. But this would be the result of negotiation and consent and nothing to do with the law. 47 Legal proposals It seemed worth ending with a short summary of the main specific proposals advanced for a new framework of labour law. They can be best grouped under six heads: i. Freedom from unfair dismissal and discrimination The restoration and extension of rights against unfair dismissal and discrimination on grounds of sex or race. ii. Freedom to withdraw labour * Restoration of the 1974 definition of a trade dispute. * Liability for contract breach and inducement to breach to be confined to action outside a trade dispute. * Restoration of the 1974 protection against the selective victimisation of strikers. * Balanced criteria for deciding applicants for labour injunctions. 111. Freedom not to work with non- unionists * After an affirmative ballot, and with exemptions on grounds of religious belief, a right to establish trade union employment areas in which new entrants and existing members are offered the choice of: (a) belonging to a union ; (b) paying the equivalent of union subscriptions to the union as a 'service fee' ; (c) paying an equivalent sum to a charity of their choice. iv. Freedom to assemble, communicate and persuade * The publication of a Code of Good Picketing Practice, providing guidelines to ensure and preserve the right to peaceful picketing -covering the activities of workers, picket leaders and the police. * The right to assemble, communicate and attempt to persuade in contemplation or furtherance of a trade dispute at or near an employer's premises -including a limited right to stop vehicles to be administered by the police. v. Freedom to represent and negotiate * Where unions are not recognised, a right for union representatives to raise grievances on behalf of members and collect union dues at the place of work -protected by a right of re-instatement if dismissed for these activities. Where 30 per cent or more of workers affected indicate that they support such action, and the employer refuses to recognise the union, a right to present wages and conditions claims and have them taken seriously by the employer. * Where 50 per cent or more of workers affected indicate that they support such action, and the employer still refuses to recognise, a right to present claims on wages, conditions and other specified issues to a form of legally binding arbitration. Where such arbitration is not followed by recognition an ultimate right to a punitive award. * The provision of ex parte legally binding arbitration machinery where it can be shown that it will contribute to the growth and mainte48 nance of collective bargaining. * A requirement that employers in low paid areas should observe relevant negotiated terms and conditions. The restoration of fair-wages clauses in all Government contracts. A provision in all Government contracts that contractors should not refuse to recognise appropriate unions with members in their employ. * Recognition criteria which encourage the reduction of inter-union competition, where appropriate, involving a 'sieve procedure' operated by the TUC vi. Freedom within trade unions * A Code of Participative Practice and minimum rule book standards with special reference to: (a) the conduct of elections; (b) the involvement of members in the formulation of policy (c) the use of industrial action; (d) the discipline and/or exclusion of members. * Rights of participation and access at the place ofwork for all unions which observe the Code of Practice, including: (a) a right to report back and consult members; (b) a right to conduct ballots and elections; (c) a right to hold meetings during working hours. Membership rights and protection against unauthorised treatment, absence of natural justice and breaches of the Code of Participative Practice. (To be enforced, in the first instance, by Industrial Tribunals.) An agenda for debate It should be stressed that these proposals are not advanced in a dogmatic spirit. Their author is only too willing to abandon one or another of them in the light of subsequent criticism. He knows that many of them are capable of improvement, while others may well be ill-advised. Undoubtedly, there are many complex and difficult problems that have been overlooked. Inevitably, a number of impractical and unwise suggestions have been proposed. One must expect and hope to be corrected with regard to matters of this sort when one sets out to promote a debate both within and outside the labour movement. The pamphlet began by recalling the arid dogmatism of the Prime Minister, which now effects all aspects of her economic and industrial policy. Labour must not emulate her example, even in its understandable reaction to policies which are designed to destroy the very basis of collective rights at work. On the contrary, in this vital area of legislation the opponents ofThatcherism will need to combine an open mind with a sense of direction. New options and possibilities must be explored, after which there must be a willingness to compromise to produce an agreement. All I have sought to provide is one possible agenda for th1s debate, together with a number of concrete suggestions about the conclusiOns that might emerge. If the result IS a programme which broadly reflects the main themes of the pamphlet 1ts author will be more than satisfied. 49 References The Politics oflnduslrial Re/a/ions, Fontana, 1979, Chapter 8. 2 See, K. Wi lliamset.al., Why are/he Brilish Bad a/ Manufacluring? Routledge, 1983. 3 Unemploymenl and Lhe Unions, 1980s: The Distorlion ofRe/alive Wages by Monopoly in !he Labour Markel, Institute of Economic Affairs, 1980. 4 Trade Unions Deslroy a Million Jobs, Journal of Economic Affairs, No. 2, January 1982, page 76. 5 I am, as always, uniquely grateful to Lord Wedderburn of Charlton for his patience and forebearance in assisting in my legal education. 6 The New Polilics ofLabour Law, in McCarthy, Trade Unions: A Book of Readings, (Second Edition), Penguin, 1985, page 510. 7 The Syslem of1nduslrial Re/a/ions in Crea / Briwin, (Ed.) Flanders and Clegg, Blackwells, 1952, Chapter2, page 117. 8 K. W. Wedderburn, The Worker and 1he Law, (First Edition), 1965, see Chapter 8. 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 See the discussion of these and related problems in The New Policies in lnduslrial Re/a/ions Law by Wedderburn. in Fosh and Littler's lnduslrial Re/a/ions and the Law in !he 1980s. Gower, 1985. especially at page 43. Broome v. DPP ( 1974), ICR 84. (H. L. ). Ka vanagh V. Hiscock, (1974) , ICR 282, D.C. V. Craig. Picke1ing and !he Law, 1975. SLT (News), pages 137-40. TUC Guides, 1979 page 14. Code ofPraclice: Pickeling, Department of Employment, 1980, page 11. TUCop.cil. , page 15. See the discussion in Labour Law: Texis and Malerials by P. Davies and M. Freedland, Weidenfield and Nicolson , 1979, Chapter7. See, R. Undy and R. Martin, Ballo1s and Trade Union Democracy, Blackwell, 1984. HMSO, 198J, page82. A NEW POCKET SIZED PAPERBACK EDITION OF THIS LABOUR MOVEMENT CLASSIC. ESSENTIAL READING £3.50 + 30p postage Fabian Society 11 Dartmouth Street SW1 edited by MICHAEL CANNELL and NORMAN CITRINE Full membership : £15 per annum entitles you to receive all the pamphlets published by the Society. You have full voting rights and can par!icipate in all the Society's activities. Pensioners. full time students. apprentices and long term unemployed are entitled to half rate membership. If you wish to receive the publications and attend seminars and schools but are not committed to our basic aims, you can become an associate (with no voting rights) at the same cost as above. Joint membership is offered to couples for the cost of a single subscription; you receive one set of literature but two voting papers. Please complete and return to: Fab1an Soc1ety, 11 Dartmouth Street, London SW1H 9BH. Further details from this address or phone 01 222 8877. Please enrol meius as full member(s) 0 or assoc1ate(s) 0 receiv1ng all pamphlets (15 LJor C7.50* and (if not over 30) make me. us member(s) of the Young Fabian Group: Date of birth ........................................................................................ . *Half rate: I am an OAP full-time student:apprentice'ilong term unemployed (delete as apprionate). I will cease full-time stud1es in .......................................................... . 1/We enclose ( ...... (cheques and postal orders payable to Fabian Society) and agree to be bound by the rules of the Society. Name .................... Address ................... .. ................ signed ........................ date .... ....... Recent Fabian Pamphets Tracts 490 David Downes 491 David Blunkett, Geoff Green 492 Keith Ewing 493 G. Bernard Shaw 494 Raymond Plant 495 Bernard Crick 496 Anthony Wright, John Stewart, Nicholas Deakin 497 earl James 498 eds . Brian Abei-Smith & PeterTownsend 499 Hugh O'Shaughnessy 500 Peter Townsend 501 Denis Healey 502 Michael Mann 503 Martin Linton 504 John Lloyd 505 David Griffiths & Chris Holmes 506 Caroline St. John-Brooks 507 ed. Lisanne Radice Special Centenary Publication Law and order: theft of an issue Building from the bottom: the Sheffield experience The Conservatives, trade unions and political funding The Fabian Society: its early history (reprinted with a preface by Melvyn Bragg) Equality, markets and the State Socialist values and time Socialism and decentralisation Occupational pensions: the failure of private welfare Social security: the real agenda Towards a democratic Central America Why are the many poor? Labour and a world society Socialism can survive: social change and the Labour Party The Swedish road to socialism Understanding the miners ' strike A new housing policy for Labour Who controls training?: the rise of the Manpower Services Commission Winning women's votes £1 .50 £1 .50 £1 .50 £1 .50 £1 .50 £1 .50 £1 .50 £1 .50 £1 .50 £1.50 £1.50 £1 .50 £1 .50 £1 .50 £2 .00 £1 .50 £1 .50 £1 .50 100 Years of Fabian Socialism £2 .50 Books available from the Fabian Society ed. Richard Silburn Patricia Pugh ed . Ben Pimlott ed . Howard Glennerster eds . M. Cannell & N. Citrine J.P.M. Millar The Future of Social Security (Fabian Society, 1985) Educate , Agitate , Organize100 years of Fabian Socialism (Methuen, 1984) Fabian Essays in Socialist Thought (Gower, 1984) The Future of the Welfare State (Heinemann, 1983) Citrine 's ABC of Chairmanship (NCLC, 1982) The Labour College Movement £2 .95 £19 .50 cased £19 .50 paper £8 .50 paper £5 .95 paper £3.50 cased £5 .50 Postage: books 50p per title (ABC of Chairmanship 30p) , The Future of Social Security and pamptilets post-free .