YOUNG FABIAN PAMPHLET 52 Is Equality Dead? ? by Michael Newton and Sean Hall with an introduction by Bernard Crick YOUNG FABIAN PAMPHLET 52 Is Equafty Dead? l 7 14 Introduction - Bernard Crick 1 Headline - Michael Newton 2 Headline - Sean Hall Bernard Crick is author of In Defence of Politics and George Orwell: a life and has also written Socialism, Socialist Values and Time (Fabian pamphlet 495) and, with David Blunkett MP, The Labour Party’s aims and values: an unofficial statement Michael Newton is a post-graduate student at University College, London Sean Hall is a post-graduate student at Birkbeck College, London This pamphlet, like all publications of the Fabian Society, represents not the collective views of the Society but only the views of the authors. The responsibility of the Society is limited to approving its publications as worthy of consideration within the Labour movement. Design: Tony Garrett November 1992 ISBN 0 7163 2052 5 ISSN 0307 7523 Printed by The College Hill Press Limited (TU), London and Worthing Published by the Fabian Society, 11 Dartmouth St, London SW1H 9BN Well, is equality dead? Bernard Crick Of course equality is dead, if by that we mean a campaigning slogan. Indeed to demand, even if one could define, equality would not win votes. But was it ever used that way? Did it ever win a single vote? I doubt. Certainly not on its own. I heard Aneurin Bevan in full cry on public platforms several times. Words like ‘welfare’, ‘common citizenship’, ‘fair shares’ and, indeed, ‘classless society’; but I can’t remember ‘equality’ as such, either naked or clothed. I suspect that it was part of the basic language that socialists used among themselves, whether or not under the old delusion that we were also speaking to the public. And as a goal it is fiendishly difficult to define, whether philosophically, sociologically or in terms of popularisable policy. But as an animating value, I believe it is far from dead. Despite all the difficulties of the concept, people have only to deny its relevance vehemently (especially in an upper class accent) to reanimate me to its defence. If we accepted it as a moral value, it would have, all economic arguments aside, revolutionary consequences for social order. If it has been buried, it has been buried alive and should be disinterred without delay. As in after the revolution, however, the judge now ends up in the dock. Asked to be one of four judges in the Young Fabian Essay competition, I was told (after a few un-Shavian drinks at the award ceremony) that I had agreed to write not merely an introduction to the two winning essays but an essay on what I think about it all. I have always hated examining, someone always gets hurt; so now the examiner. Certainly examining has nothing to do with equality; on the contrary, it seeks for the best or to create a full-blown hierarchy according to the conventional rules of a competition. Orwell once remarked, a propos Professor Hayek, that the trouble with competitions is that someone has to win them. Fortunately social life is not just one big competition. I am sure that Professor Hayek or even Professor Scruton have enjoyed some domestic tranquility or non-competitive relationships; at least I hope they have, for I bear them no ill-will as human beings entitled to an equality of respect simply because they are human, though not to an equality of praise unless what they have said merits it. Let me stress that these are essays not monographs or blue-prints for 1 policy. Michael Newton puts this very well: ‘An essay bears the same relationship to ‘Truth’ as our unequal personalities bear to our equal natures. An essay survives in a world of appearances, and it is not Holy Writ. An essay describes and enacts the process of our thoughts. It is a trial of our intellect, a casual reaching towards an idea, and never the expression of the idea itself.’ I only quibble that ‘casual’ is too casual a word, or if an irony against all those who have the answer to the social question, then the irony may be lost on Fabian folk more serious than myself. ‘Speculative’ is the better word. Essays raise possibilities and try to force us or entice us to open-up and think openly. Sean Hall begins with the proper complaint that: ‘The Labour Party in Britain has traditionally placed action above contemplation, practice above theory... (This) has led to a neglect of the theoretical support without which political practice is either muddled or confined to pragmatic drift... It has meant that socialist values have been either ill-defined or not defined at all. What is required, then, is an awakening of our curiosity in theory. For a better theory can make a better practice.’ That is a fine statement, and speaks for most of the essays the four judges read; the short-list seemed to enjoy thinking it out for themselves, apart from a few heavies who regurgitated the academic literature on equality. Somehow the question as set incited a revolt of the young, theorising furiously against the old Fabian tradition of empiricism; but again I would quibble mildly and wish that Sean Hall had written the plural ‘theories’ rather than singular ‘theory’. Marxism became too rigid by believing either that there had been one true theory, that popularisation and compromise had withered away, or that ‘the method’ if pursued resolutely with blinkered intelligence would on some great day yield a definitive ‘Marxism for our times’. It became very introverted, narcissistic indeed. Ernest Gellner some years ago mocked those who solemnly said, for instance, that ‘nationalism poses a problem for Marxist theory’. It happens to pose a problem for the world. What about socialism? Before we can get near a theory of democratic socialism, we need to recover the habit of thinking deeply, which actually means thinking simply; not making or accepting complicated or conventional assumptions, but asking what the very preconception of an activity is. Anyone trained in a tradition of thought can write, if they care, a Ph.D.; but few have the Rousseauistic innocence or audacity to question and illuminate basic assumptions. That is why I find Michael Newton’s essay so unusual and so impressive, although I fear that some Fabians will ask, ‘what has this got to do with the Labour Party or socialism; what does he stand for?’ Let me try to answer as I see it. He is saying that equality is rooted in 2 human nature, ‘the world of being..., all that is internal, private, and incommunicable’ (again I would prefer, I can be a terrible pedant, ‘incommensurable’ to ‘incommunicable’); but the world of human affairs is very different, it is inherently unequal. We see ourselves as equal but all practical activities as rooted in or resulting in inequality. If anyone doubts this bleak assumption just suppose, imaginatively, that a benign iron regime imposed an exactly equal distribution of property and income; to keep it that way, it would then have to legislate against any scope for the exercise of talent, greed or covetousness - trading of any kind, buying or selling personal possessions, allotments, swaping even; and luck as well as lotteries would have to be abolished. Well, what is all this abstract nonsense? Whoever believed in equality of result anyway, or even (the more awkward consideration for the Fabian tradition) that equality of opportunity would not soon create a new class system? So it is as well to throw the chimera of literal equality out of the window before, as I think we should, we try to reinstate equality as dominant value. Equal worth For equality must be rooted in how we treat each other as persons, in whether we genuinely see all others as equals, as of equal worth. Common humanity is not so much what we have in common with each other in some physical, anthropological or sociological sense, but how we recognise morally others, strangers especially, to be equally human. What creates social bonding at all among totally unique individuals is precisely a mutual recognition of common humanity. I do not believe that market liberals and old Tories find it at all easy to recognise others as truly equal (except occasionally as Anglican souls); they see the exercise of individual talents as creating differential worth; and material or social success is good evidence of worth. It is so easy to fall into that trap. Some democratic socialists fell into it: the good old doing good for others, the less worthy. ‘We are all here on earth to help each other’, said Auden, ‘but what the others are here for, god only knows’. We can only diminish unjustifiable inequalities in the real world if (a) we stop pursuing chimeras and (b) are as solid as a rock about human equality. If equality as a goal is unreachable, a receding horizon at best, equality as a value or a standard of conduct could and should govern most aspects of our lives. Thinking about human nature in a manner that might be familiar to any who have read, easily enough, Michael Ignatieffs The Needs of Strangers, or wrestled manfully with Hannah Arendt’s The Human Condition, Michael Newton helps finally to settle my conviction that any democratic socialism must be built on a moral perception of human equality, rather than on economic arguments. Both are needed but the horse must go in front of the cart. Arendt had argued that laisser faire liberalism and Marxism grew up together, like quarreling siblings, sharing a gross exaggeration of the degree to which economic structures necessarily shape and dominate, human 3 behaviour. Human actions are not economically determined; we can exercise more freedom than we have often supposed. The economy limits, conditions or enables but it does not determine our actions. As Karl Popper argued, social lawS( are conditional not causal; generalisations about society have different degrees of probability, none are necessarily and universally true. An important conclusion must follow from this: that if there is the care and the will, markets can be civilised by the culture in which they operate, by laws, even by the care and compassion that individuals have for each other. Orwell was mocked by Marxists for drawing commonsense distinctions between ‘the decent employer’ and ‘the remote and uncaring boss’; even for using terms like ‘decency’ and ‘fairness’ so often (so casually?). But they are the popular moral perceptions to which, I think, Mr Newton wants us to stay close. The foundation cannot be neglected. Everything we might wish to achieve must be built on the moral conviction that all men and women are equally worthy. There is no incompatibility between liberty and equality here, indeed they are simply the two dimensions of basic humanity: the liberty that follows from the uniqueness of individuals but also the equality of recognition and respect that creates sociability. Arendt put it this way: there is nothing in the world more like one human being than another, but also nothing more different. But when we move into the world of institutions and interests, away from the individual to social questions, then obviously equality and liberty are in perpetual tension andhcan